Writings of Augustine. On the Trinity, De Trinitate
Advanced Information
The Fifteen Books of Aurelius Augustinus, Bishop of Hippo,
on the Trinity, de Trinitate
Translated by the Rev. Arthur West Haddan, B.D.,
Hon. Canon of Worchester, and Rector of Barton-on-the-Heath,
Warwickshire.
Published in 1886 by Philip Schaff,
New York: Christian Literature Publishing Co.
.
Book VIII.
Explains and proves that not only the Father is not greater than the
Son, but neither are both together anything greater than the Holy
Spirit, nor any two together in the same trinity anything greater than
one, nor all three together anything greater than each severally. It
is then shown how the nature itself of God may be understood from our
understanding of truth, and from our knowledge of the supreme good,
and from the innate love of righteousness, whereby a righteous soul is
loved even by a soul that is itself not yet righteous. But it is urged
above all, that the knowledge of God is to be sought by love, which
God is said to be in the Scriptures; and in this love is also pointed
out the existence of some trace of a trinity.
Preface.--The Conclusion of What Has Been Said Above. The Rule to Be
Observed in the More Difficult Questions of the Faith.
We have said elsewhere that those things are predicated specially in
the Trinity as belonging severally to each person, which are
predicated relatively the one to the other, as Father and Son, and the
gift of both, the Holy Spirit; for the Father is not the Trinity, nor
the Son the Trinity, nor the gift the Trinity: but what whenever each
is singly spoken of in respect to themselves, then they are not spoken
of as three in the plural number, but one, the Trinity itself, as the
Father God, the Son God, and the Holy Spirit God; the Father good, the
Son good, and the Holy Spirit good; and the Father omnipotent, the Son
omnipotent, and the Holy Spirit omnipotent: yet neither three Gods,
nor three goods, nor three omnipotents, but one God, good, omnipotent,
the Trinity itself; and whatsoever else is said of them not relatively
in respect to each other, but individually in respect to themselves.
For they are thus spoken of according to essence, since in them to be
is the same as to be great, as to be good, as to be wise, and whatever
else is said of each person individually therein, or of the Trinity
itself, in respect to themselves. And that therefore they are called
three persons, or three substances, not in order that any difference
of essence may be understood, but that we may be able to answer by
some one word, should any one ask what three, or what three things?
And that there is so great an equality in that Trinity, that not only
the Father is not greater than the Son, as regards divinity, but
neither are the Father and Son together greater than the Holy Spirit;
nor is each individual person, whichever it be of the three, less than
the Trinity itself. This is what we have said; and if it is handled
and repeated frequently, it becomes, no doubt, more familiarly known:
yet some limit, too, must be put to the discussion, and we must
supplicate God with most devout piety, that He will open our
understanding, and take away the inclination of disputing, in order
that our minds may discern the essence of the truth, that has neither
bulk nor moveableness. Now, therefore, so far as the Creator Himself
aids us in His marvellous mercy, let us consider these subjects, into
which we will enter more deeply than we entered into those which
preceded, although they are in truth the same; preserving the while
this rule, that what has not yet been made clear to our intellect, be
nevertheless not loosened from the firmness of our faith.
|
|
Chapter 1.--It is Shown by Reason that in God Three are Not Anything
Greater Than One Person.
2. For we say that in this Trinity two or three persons are not
anything greater than one of them; which carnal perception does not
receive, for no other reason except because it perceives as it can the
true things which are created, but cannot discern the truth itself by
which they are created; for if it could, then the very corporeal light
would in no way be more clear than this which we have said. For in
respect to the substance of truth, since it alone truly is, nothing is
greater, unless because it more truly is. [662] But in respect to
whatsoever is intelligible and unchangeable, no one thing is more
truly than another, since all alike are unchangeably eternal; and that
which therein is called great, is not great from any other source than
from that by which it truly is. Wherefore, where magnitude itself is
truth, whatsoever has more of magnitude must needs have more of truth;
whatsoever therefore has not more of truth, has not also more of
magnitude. Further, whatsoever has more of truth is certainly more
true, just as that is greater which has more of magnitude; therefore
in respect to the substance of truth that is more great which is more
true. But the Father and the Son together are not more truly than the
Father singly, or the Son singly. Both together, therefore, are not
anything greater than each of them singly. And since also the Holy
Spirit equally is truly, the Father and Son together are not anything
greater than He, since neither are they more truly. The Father also
and the Holy Spirit together, since they do not surpass the Son in
truth (for they are not more truly), do not surpass Him either in
magnitude. And so the Son and the Holy Spirit together are just as
great as the Father alone, since they are as truly. So also the
Trinity itself is as great as each several person therein. For where
truth itself is magnitude, that is not more great which is not more
true: since in regard to the essence of truth, to be true is the same
as to be, and to be is the same as to be great; therefore to be great
is the same as to be true. And in regard to it, therefore, what is
equally true must needs also be equally great.
Footnotes
[662] [In this and the following chapter, the meaning of Augustin will
be clearer, if the Latin "veritas," "vera," and "vere," are rendered
occasionally, by "reality," "real," and "really." He is endeavoring to
prove the equality of the three persons, by the fact that they are
equally real (true), and the degree of their reality (truth) is the
same. Real being is true being; reality is truth. In common
phraseology, truth and reality are synonymous.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 2.--Every Corporeal Conception Must Be Rejected, in Order that
It May Be Understood How God is Truth.
3. But in respect to bodies, it may be the case that this gold and
that gold may be equally true [real], but this may be greater than
that, since magnitude is not the same thing in this case as truth; and
it is one thing for it to be gold, another to be great. So also in the
nature of the soul; a soul is not called great in the same respect in
which it is called true. For he, too, has a true [real] soul who has
not a great soul; since the essence of body and soul is not the
essence of the truth [reality] itself; as is the Trinity, one God,
alone, great, true, truthful, the truth. Of whom if we endeavor to
think, so far as He Himself permits and grants, let us not think of
any touch or embrace in local space, as if of three bodies, or of any
compactness of conjunction, as fables tell of three-bodied Geryon; but
let whatsoever may occur to the mind, that is of such sort as to be
greater in three than in each singly, and less in one than in two, be
rejected without any doubt; for so everything corporeal is rejected.
But also in spiritual things let nothing changeable that may have
occurred to the mind be thought of God. For when we aspire from this
depth to that height, it is a step towards no small knowledge, if,
before we can know what God is, we can already know what He is not.
For certainly He is neither earth nor heaven; nor, as it were, earth
and heaven; nor any such thing as we see in the heaven; nor any such
thing as we do not see, but which perhaps is in heaven. Neither if you
were to magnify in the imagination of your thought the light of the
sun as much as you are able, either that it may be greater, or that it
may be brighter, a thousand times as much, or times without number;
neither is this God. Neither as [663] we think of the pure angels as
spirits animating celestial bodies, and changing and dealing with them
after the will by which they serve God; not even if all, and there are
"thousands of thousands," [664] were brought together into one, and
became one; neither is any such thing God. Neither if you were to
think of the same spirits as without bodies--a thing indeed most
difficult for carnal thought to do. Behold and see, if thou canst, O
soul pressed down by the corruptible body, and weighed down by earthly
thoughts, many and various; behold and see, if thou canst, that God is
truth. [665] For it is written that "God is light;" [666] not in such
way as these eyes see, but in such way as the heart sees, when it is
said, He is truth [reality]. Ask not what is truth [reality] for
immediately the darkness of corporeal images and the clouds of
phantasms will put themselves in the way, and will disturb that calm
which at the first twinkling shone forth to thee, when I said truth
[reality]. See that thou remainest, if thou canst, in that first
twinkling with which thou art dazzled, as it were, by a flash, when it
is said to thee, Truth [Reality]. But thou canst not; thou wilt glide
back into those usual and earthly things. And what weight, pray, is it
that will cause thee so to glide back, unless it be the bird-lime of
the stains of appetite thou hast contracted, and the errors of thy
wandering from the right path?
Footnotes
[663] Read si for sicut, if for as. Bened. ed.
[664] Apoc. v. 11
[665] Wisd. ix. 15
[666] 1 John i. 5
Chapter 3.--How God May Be Known to Be the Chief Good. The Mind Does
Not Become Good Unless by Turning to God.
4. Behold again, and see if thou canst. Thou certainly dost not love
anything except what is good, since good is the earth, with the
loftiness of its mountains, and the due measure of its hills, and the
level surface of its plains; and good is an estate that is pleasant
and fertile; and good is a house that is arranged in due proportions,
and is spacious and bright; and good are animal and animate bodies;
and good is air that is temperate, and salubrious; and good is food
that is agreeable and fit for health; and good is health, without
pains or lassitude; and good is the countenance of man that is
disposed in fit proportions, and is cheerful in look, and bright in
color; and good is the mind of a friend, with the sweetness of
agreement, and with the confidence of love; and good is a righteous
man; and good are riches, since they are readily useful; and good is
the heaven, with its sun, and moon, and stars; and good are the
angels, by their holy obedience; and good is discourse that sweetly
teaches and suitably admonishes the hearer; and good is a poem that is
harmonious in its numbers and weighty in its sense. And why add yet
more and more? This thing is good and that good, but take away this
and that, and regard good itself if thou canst; so wilt thou see God,
not good by a good that is other than Himself, but the good of all
good. For in all these good things, whether those which I have
mentioned, or any else that are to be discerned or thought, we could
not say that one was better than another, when we judge truly, unless
a conception of the good itself had been impressed upon us, such that
according to it we might both approve some things as good, and prefer
one good to another. So God is to be loved, not this and that good,
but the good itself. For the good that must be sought for the soul is
not one above which it is to fly by judging, but to which it is to
cleave by loving; and what can this be except God? Not a good mind, or
a good angel, or the good heaven, but the good good. For perhaps what
I wish to say may be more easily perceived in this way. For when, for
instance, a mind is called good, as there are two words, so from these
words I understand two things--one whereby it is mind, and another
whereby it is good. And itself had no share in making itself a mind,
for there was nothing as yet to make itself to be anything; but to
make itself to be a good mind, I see, must be brought about by the
will: not because that by which it is mind is not itself anything
good;--for how else is it already called, and most truly called,
better than the body?--but it is not yet called a good mind, for this
reason, that the action of the will still is wanted, by which it is to
become more excellent; and if it has neglected this, then it is justly
blamed, and is rightly called not a good mind. For it then differs
from the mind which does perform this; and since the latter is
praiseworthy, the former doubtless, which does not perform, it is
blameable. But when it does this of set purpose, and becomes a good
mind, it yet cannot attain to being so unless it turn itself to
something which itself is not. And to what can it turn itself that it
may become a good mind, except to the good which it loves, and seeks,
and obtains? And if it turns itself back again from this, and becomes
not good, then by the very act of turning away from the good, unless
that good remain in it from which it turns away, it cannot again turn
itself back thither if it should wish to amend.
5. Wherefore there would be no changeable goods, unless there were the
unchangeable good. Whenever then thou art told of this good thing and
that good thing, which things can also in other respects be called not
good, if thou canst put aside those things which are good by the
participation of the good, and discern that good itself by the
participation of which they are good (for when this or that good thing
is spoken of, thou understandest together with them the good itself
also): if, then, I say thou canst remove these things, and canst
discern the good in itself, then thou wilt have discerned God. And if
thou shalt cleave to Him with love, thou shalt be forthwith blessed.
But whereas other things are not loved, except because they are good,
be ashamed, in cleaving to them, not to love the good itself whence
they are good. That also, which is a mind, only because it is a mind,
while it is not yet also good by the turning itself to the
unchangeable good, but, as I said, is only a mind; whenever it so
pleases us, as that we prefer it even, if we understand aright, to all
corporeal light, does not please us in itself, but in that skill by
which it was made. For it is thence approved as made, wherein it is
seen to have been to be made. This is truth, and simple good: for it
is nothing else than the good itself, and for this reason also the
chief good. For no good can be diminished or increased, except that
which is good from some other good. Therefore the mind turns itself,
in order to be good, to that by which it comes to be a mind. Therefore
the will is then in harmony with nature, so that the mind may be
perfected in good, when that good is loved by the turning of the will
to it, whence that other good also comes which is not lost by the
turning away of the will from it. For by turning itself from the chief
good, the mind loses the being a good mind; but it does not lose the
being a mind. And this, too, is a good already, and one better than
the body. The will, therefore, loses that which the will obtains. For
the mind already was, that could wish to be turned to that from which
it was: but that as yet was not, that could wish to be before it was.
And herein is our [supreme] good, when we see whether the thing ought
to be or to have been, respecting which we comprehend that it ought to
be or to have been, and when we see that the thing could not have been
unless it ought to have been, of which we also do not comprehend in
what manner it ought to have been. This good then is not far from
every one of us: for in it we live, and move, and have our being.
[667]
Footnotes
[667] Acts xvii. 27, 28
Chapter 4.--God Must First Be Known by an Unerring Faith, that He May
Be Loved.
6. But it is by love that we must stand firm to this and cleave to
this, in order that we may enjoy the presence of that by which we are,
and in the absence of which we could not be at all. For as "we walk as
yet by faith, and not by sight," [668] we certainly do not yet see
God, as the same [apostle] saith, "face to face:" [669] whom however
we shall never see, unless now already we love. But who loves what he
does not know? For it is possible something may be known and not
loved: but I ask whether it is possible that what is not known can be
loved; since if it cannot, then no one loves God before he knows Him.
And what is it to know God except to behold Him and steadfastly
perceive Him with the mind? For He is not a body to be searched out by
carnal eyes. But before also that we have power to behold and to
perceive God, as He can be beheld and perceived, which is permitted to
the pure in heart; for "blessed are the pure in heart. for they shall
see God;" [670] except He is loved by faith, it will not be possible
for the heart to be cleansed, in order that it may be apt and meet to
see Him. For where are there those three, in order to build up which
in the mind the whole apparatus of the divine Scriptures has been
raised up, namely Faith, Hope, and Charity, [671] except in a mind
believing what it does not yet see, and hoping and loving what it
believes? Even He therefore who is not known, but yet is believed, can
be loved. But indisputably we must take care, lest the mind believing
that which it does not see, feign to itself something which is not,
and hope for and love that which is false. For in that case, it will
not be charity out of a pure heart, and of a good conscience, and of
faith unfeigned, which is the end of the commandment, as the same
apostle says. [672]
7. But it must needs be, that, when by reading or hearing of them we
believe in any corporeal things which we have not seen, the mind
frames for itself something under bodily features and forms, just as
it may occur to our thoughts; which either is not true, or even if it
be true, which can most rarely happen, yet this is of no benefit to us
to believe in by faith, but it is useful for some other purpose, which
is intimated by means of it. For who is there that reads or hears what
the Apostle Paul has written, or what has been written of him, that
does not imagine to himself the countenance both of the apostle
himself, and of all those whose names are there mentioned? And
whereas, among such a multitude of men to whom these books are known,
each imagines in a different way those bodily features and forms, it
is assuredly uncertain which it is that imagines them more nearly and
more like the reality. Nor, indeed, is our faith busied therein with
the bodily countenance of those men; but only that by the grace of God
they so lived and so acted as that Scripture witnesses: this it is
which it is both useful to believe, and which must not be despaired
of, and must be sought. For even the countenance of our Lord Himself
in the flesh is variously fancied by the diversity of countless
imaginations, which yet was one, whatever it was. Nor in our faith
which we have of our Lord Jesus Christ, is that wholesome which the
mind imagines for itself, perhaps far other than the reality, but that
which we think of man according to his kind: for we have a notion of
human nature implanted in us, as it were by rule, according to which
we know forthwith, that whatever such thing we see is a man or the
form of a man.
Footnotes
[668] 2 Cor. v. 7
[669] 1 Cor. xiii. 12
[670] Matt. v. 8
[671] 1 Cor. xiii. 13
[672] 1 Tim. i. 5
Chapter 5.--How the Trinity May Be Loved Though Unknown.
Our conception is framed according to this notion, when we believe
that God was made man for us, as an example of humility, and to show
the love of God towards us. For this it is which it is good for us to
believe, and to retain firmly and unshakenly in our heart, that the
humility by which God was born of a woman, and was led to death
through contumelies so great by mortal men, is the chiefest remedy by
which the swelling of our pride may be cured, and the profound mystery
by which the bond of sin may be loosed. So also, because we know what
omnipotence is, we believe concerning the omnipotent God in the power
of His miracles and of His resurrection, and we frame conceptions
respecting actions of this kind, according to the species and genera
of things that are either ingrafted in us by nature, or gathered by
experience, that our faith may not be feigned. For neither do we know
the countenance of the Virgin Mary; from whom, untouched by a husband,
nor tainted in the birth itself, He was wonderfully born. Neither have
we seen what were the lineaments of the body of Lazarus; nor yet
Bethany; nor the sepulchre, and that stone which He commanded to be
removed when He raised Him from the dead; nor the new tomb cut out in
the rock, whence He Himself arose; nor the Mount of Olives, from
whence He ascended into heaven. And, in short, whoever of us have not
seen these things, know not whether they are as we conceive them to
be, nay judge them more probably not to be so. For when the aspect
either of a place, or a man, or of any other body, which we happened
to imagine before we saw it, turns out to be the same when it occurs
to our sight as it was when it occurred to our mind, we are moved with
no little wonder. So scarcely and hardly ever does it happen. And yet
we believe those things most steadfastly, because we imagine them
according to a special and general notion, of which we are certain.
For we believe our Lord Jesus Christ to be born of a virgin who was
called Mary. But what a virgin is, or what it is to be born, and what
is a proper name, we do not believe, but certainly know. And whether
that was the countenance of Mary which occurred to the mind in
speaking of those things or recollecting them, we neither know at all,
nor believe. It is allowable, then, in this case to say without
violation of the faith, perhaps she had such or such a countenance,
perhaps she had not: but no one could say without violation of the
Christian faith, that perhaps Christ was born of a virgin.
8. Wherefore, since we desire to understand the eternity, and
equality, and unity of the Trinity, as much as is permitted us, but
ought to believe before we understand; and since we must watch
carefully, that our faith be not feigned; since we must have the
fruition of the same Trinity, that we may live blessedly; but if we
have believed anything false of it, our hope would be worthless, and
our charity not pure: how then can we love, by believing, that Trinity
which we do not know? Is it according to the special or general
notion, according to which we love the Apostle Paul? In whose case,
even if he was not of that countenance which occurs to us when we
think of him (and this we do not know at all), yet we know what a man
is. For not to go far away, this we are; and it is manifest he, too,
was this, and that his soul joined to his body lived after the manner
of mortals. Therefore we believe this of him, which we find in
ourselves, according to the species or genus under which all human
nature alike is comprised. What then do we know, whether specially or
generally, of that most excellent Trinity, as if there were many such
trinities, some of which we had learned by experience, so that we may
believe that Trinity, too, to have been such as they, through the rule
of similitude, impressed upon us, whether a special or a general
notion; and thus love also that thing which we believe and do not yet
know, from the parity of the thing which we do know? But this
certainly is not so. Or is it that, as we love in our Lord Jesus
Christ, that He rose from the dead, although we never saw any one rise
from thence, so we can believe in and love the Trinity which we do not
see, and the like of which we never have seen? But we certainly know
what it is to die, and what it is to live; because we both live, and
from time to time have seen and experienced both dead and dying
persons. And what else is it to rise again, except to live again, that
is, to return to life from death? When, therefore, we say and believe
that there is a Trinity, we know what a Trinity is, because we know
what three are; but this is not what we love. For we can easily have
this whenever we will, to pass over other things, by just holding up
three fingers. Or do we indeed love, not every trinity, but the
Trinity, that is God? We love then in the Trinity, that it is God: but
we never saw or knew any other God, because God is One; He alone whom
we have not yet seen, and whom we love by believing. But the question
is, from what likeness or comparison of known things can we believe,
in order that we may love God, whom we do not yet know?
Chapter 6.--How the Man Not Yet Righteous Can Know the Righteous Man
Whom He Loves.
9. Return then with me, and let us consider why we love the apostle.
Is it at all on account of his human kind, which we know right well,
in that we believe him to have been a man? Assuredly not; for if it
were so, he now is not him whom we love, since he is no longer that
man, for his soul is separated from his body. But we believe that
which we love in him to be still living, for we love his righteous
mind. From what general or special rule then, except that we know both
what a mind is, and what it is to be righteous? And we say, indeed,
not unfitly, that we therefore know what a mind is, because we too
have a mind. For neither did we ever see it with our eyes, and gather
a special or general notion from the resemblance of more minds than
one, which we had seen; but rather, as I have said before, because we
too have it. For what is known so intimately, and so perceives itself
to be itself, as that by which also all other things are perceived,
that is, the mind itself? For we recognize the movements of bodies
also, by which we perceive that others live besides ourselves, from
the resemblance of ourselves; since we also so move our body in living
as we observe those bodies to be moved. For even when a living body is
moved, there is no way opened to our eyes to see the mind, a thing
which cannot be seen by the eyes; but we perceive something to be
contained in that bulk, such as is contained in ourselves, so as to
move in like manner our own bulk, which is the life and the soul.
Neither is this, as it were, the property of human foresight and
reason, since brute animals also perceive that not only they
themselves live, but also other brute animals interchangeably, and the
one the other, and that we ourselves do so. Neither do they see our
souls, save from the movements of the body, and that immediately and
most easily by some natural agreement. Therefore we both know the mind
of any one from our own, and believe also from our own of him whom we
do not know. For not only do we perceive that there is a mind, but we
can also know what a mind is, by reflecting upon our own: for we have
a mind. But whence do we know what a righteous man is? For we said
above that we love the apostle for no other reason except that he is a
righteous mind. We know, then, what a righteous man also is, just as
we know what a mind is. But what a mind is, as has been said, we know
from ourselves, for there is a mind in us. But whence do we know what
a righteous man is, if we are not righteous? But if no one but he who
is righteous knows what is a righteous man, no one but a righteous man
loves a righteous man; for one cannot love him whom one believes to be
righteous, for this very reason that one does believe him to be
righteous, if one does not know what it is to be righteous; according
to that which we have shown above, that no one loves what he believes
and does not see, except by some rule of a general or special notion.
And if for this reason no one but a righteous man loves a righteous
man, how will any one wish to be a righteous man who is not yet so?
For no one wishes to be that which he does not love. But, certainly,
that he who is not righteous may be so, it is necessary that he should
wish to be righteous; and in order that he may wish to be righteous,
he loves the righteous man. Therefore, even he who is not yet
righteous, loves the righteous man. [673] But he cannot love the
righteous man, who is ignorant what a righteous man is. Accordingly,
even he who is not yet righteous, knows what a righteous man is.
Whence then does he know this? Does he see it with his eyes? Is any
corporeal thing righteous, as it is white, or black, or square, or
round? Who could say this? Yet with one's eyes one has seen nothing
except corporeal things. But there is nothing righteous in a man
except the mind; and when a man is called a righteous man, he is
called so from the mind, not from the body. For righteousness is in
some sort the beauty of the mind, by which men are beautiful; very
many too who are misshapen and deformed in body. And as the mind is
not seen with the eyes, so neither is its beauty. From whence then
does he who is not yet righteous know what a righteous man is, and
love the righteous man that he may become righteous? Do certain signs
shine forth by the motion of the body, by which this or that man is
manifested to be righteous? But whence does any one know that these
are the signs of a righteous mind when he is wholly ignorant what it
is to be righteous? Therefore he does know. But whence do we know what
it is to be righteous, even when we are not yet righteous? If we know
from without ourselves, we know it by some bodily thing. But this is
not a thing of the body. Therefore we know in ourselves what it is to
be righteous. For I find this nowhere else when I seek to utter it,
except within myself; and if I ask another what it is to be righteous,
he seeks within himself what to answer; and whosoever hence can answer
truly, he has found within himself what to answer. And when indeed I
wish to speak of Carthage, I seek within myself what to speak, and I
find within myself a notion or image of Carthage; but I have received
this through the body, that is, through the perception of the body,
since I have been present in that city in the body, and I saw and
perceived it, and retained it in my memory, that I might find within
myself a word concerning it, whenever I might wish to speak of it. For
its word is the image itself of it in my memory, not that sound of two
syllables when Carthage is named, or even when that name itself is
thought of silently from time to time, but that which I discern in my
mind, when I utter that dissyllable with my voice, or even before I
utter it. So also, when I wish to speak of Alexandria, which I never
saw, an image of it is present with me. For whereas I had heard from
many and had believed that city to be great, in such way as it could
be told me, I formed an image of it in my mind as I was able; and this
is with me its word when I wish to speak of it, before I utter with my
voice the five syllables which make the name that almost every one
knows. And yet if I could bring forth that image from my mind to the
eyes of men who know Alexandria, certainly all either would say, It is
not it; or if they said, It is, I should greatly wonder; and as I
gazed at it in my mind, that is, at the image which was as it were its
picture, I should yet not know it to be it, but should believe those
who retained an image they had seen. But I do not so ask what it is to
be righteous, nor do I so find it, nor do I so gaze upon it, when I
utter it; neither am I so approved when I am heard, nor do I so
approve when I hear; as though I have seen such a thing with my eyes,
or learned it by some perception of the body, or heard it from those
who had so learned it. For when I say, and say knowingly, that mind is
righteous which knowingly and of purpose assigns to every one his due
in life and behavior, I do not think of anything absent, as Carthage,
or imagine it as I am able, as Alexandria, whether it be so or not;
but I discern something present, and I discern it within myself,
though I myself am not that which I discern; and many if they hear
will approve it. And whoever hears me and knowingly approves, he too
discerns this same thing within himself, even though he himself be not
what he discerns. But when a righteous man says this, he discerns and
says that which he himself is. And whence also does he discern it,
except within himself? But this is not to be wondered at; for whence
should he discern himself except within himself? The wonderful thing
is, that the mind should see within itself that which it has seen
nowhere else, and should see truly, and should see the very true
righteous mind, and should itself be a mind, and yet not a righteous
mind, which nevertheless it sees within itself. Is there another mind
that is righteous in a mind that is not yet righteous? Or if there is
not, what does it there see when it sees and says what is a righteous
mind, nor sees it anywhere else but in itself, when itself is not a
righteous mind? Is that which it sees an inner truth present to the
mind which has power to behold it? Yet all have not that power; and
they who have power to behold it, are not all also that which they
behold, that is, they are not also righteous minds themselves, just as
they are able to see and to say what is a righteous mind. And whence
will they be able to be so, except by cleaving to that very same form
itself which they behold, so that from thence they may be formed and
may be righteous minds; not only discerning and saying that the mind
is righteous which knowingly and of purpose assigns to every one that
which is his due in life and behavior, but so likewise that they
themselves may live righteously and be righteous in character, by
assigning to every one that which is his due, so as to owe no man
anything, but to love one another. [674] And whence can any one cleave
to that form but by loving it? Why then do we love another whom we
believe to be righteous, and do not love that form itself wherein we
see what is a righteous mind, that we also may be able to be
righteous? Is it that unless we loved that also, we should not love
him at all, whom through it we love; but whilst we are not righteous,
we love that form too little to allow of our being able to be
righteous? The man therefore who is believed to be righteous, is loved
through that form and truth which he who loves discerns and
understands within himself; but that very form and truth itself cannot
be loved from any other source than itself. For we do not find any
other such thing besides itself, so that by believing we might love it
when it is unknown, in that we here already know another such thing.
For whatsoever of such a kind one may have seen, is itself; and there
is not any other such thing, since itself alone is such as itself is.
He therefore who loves men, ought to love them either because they are
righteous, or that they may become righteous. For so also he ought to
love himself, either because he is righteous, or that he may become
righteous; for in this way he loves his neighbor as himself without
any risk. For he who loves himself otherwise, loves himself
wrongfully, since he loves himself to this end that he may be
unrighteous; therefore to this end that he may be wicked; and hence it
follows next that he does not love himself; for, "He who loveth
iniquity, [675] hateth his own soul." [676]
Footnotes
[673] [The "wish" and "love" which Augustin here attributes to the
non-righteous man is not true and spiritual, but selfish. In chapter
vii. 10, he speaks of true love as distinct from that kind of desire
which is a mere wish. The latter he calls cupiditas. "That is to be
called love which is true, otherwise it is desire (cupiditas); and so
those who desire (cupidi) are improperly said to love (diligere), just
as they who love (diligunt) are said improperly to desire
(cupere)."--W.G.T.S.]
[674] Rom. xiii. 8
[675] Violence--A.V.
[676] Ps. xi. 6
Chapter 7.--Of True Love, by Which We Arrive at the Knowledge of the
Trinity. God is to Be Sought, Not Outwardly, by Seeking to Do
Wonderful Things with the Angels, But Inwardly, by Imitating the Piety
of Good Angels.
10. No other thing, then, is chiefly to be regarded in this inquiry,
which we make concerning the Trinity and concerning knowing God,
except what is true love, nay, rather what is love. For that is to be
called love which is true, otherwise it is desire; and so those who
desire are said improperly to love, just as they who love are said
improperly to desire. But this is true love, that cleaving to the
truth we may live righteously, and so may despise all mortal things in
comparison with the love of men, whereby we wish them to live
righteously. For so we should be prepared also to die profitably for
our brethren, as our Lord Jesus Christ taught us by His example. For
as there are two commandments on which hang all the Law and the
prophets, love of God and love of our neighbor; [677] not without
cause the Scripture mostly puts one for both: whether it be of God
only, as is that text, "For we know that all things work together for
good to them that love God;" [678] and again, "But if any man love
God, the same is known of Him;" [679] and that, "Because the love of
God is shed abroad in our hearts by the Holy Ghost which is given unto
us;" [680] and many other passages; because he who loves God must both
needs do what God has commanded, and loves Him just in such proportion
as he does so; therefore he must needs also love his neighbor, because
God has commanded it: or whether it be that Scripture only mentions
the love of our neighbor, as in that text, "Bear ye one another's
burdens, and so fulfill the law of Christ;" [681] and again, "For all
the law is fulfilled in one word, even in this, Thou shalt love thy
neighbor as thyself;" [682] and in the Gospel, "All things whatsoever
ye would that men should do to you, do ye even so to them; for this is
the Law and the prophets." [683] And many other passages occur in the
sacred writings, in which only the love of our neighbor seems to be
commanded for perfection, while the love of God is passed over in
silence; whereas the Law and the prophets hang on both precepts. But
this, too, is because he who loves his neighbor must needs also love
above all else love itself. But "God is love; and he that dwelleth in
love, dwelleth in God." [684] Therefore he must needs above all else
love God.
11. Wherefore they who seek God through those Powers which rule over
the world, or parts of the world, are removed and cast away far from
Him; not by intervals of space, but by difference of affections: for
they endeavor to find a path outwardly, and forsake their own inward
things, within which is God. Therefore, even although they may either
have heard some holy heavenly Power, or in some way or another may
have thought of it, yet they rather covet its deeds at which human
weakness marvels, but do not imitate the piety by which divine rest is
acquired. For they prefer, through pride, to be able to do that which
an angel does, more than, through devotion, to be that which an angel
is. For no holy being rejoices in his own power, but in His from whom
he has the power which he fitly can have; and he knows it to be more a
mark of power to be united to the Omnipotent by a pious will, than to
be able, by his own power and will, to do what they may tremble at who
are not able to do such things. Therefore the Lord Jesus Christ
Himself, in doing such things, in order that He might teach better
things to those who marvelled at them, and might turn those who were
intent and in doubt about unusual temporal things to eternal and inner
things, says, "Come unto me, all ye that labor and are heavy laden,
and I will give you rest. Take my yoke upon you." And He does not say,
Learn of me, because I raise those who have been dead four days; but
He says, "Learn of me; for I am meek and lowly in heart." For
humility, which is most solid, is more powerful and safer than pride,
that is most inflated. And so He goes on to say, "And ye shall find
rest unto your souls," [685] for "Love [686] is not puffed up;" [687]
and "God is Love;" [688] and "such as be faithful in love shall rest
in [689] Him," [690] called back from the din which is without to
silent joys. Behold, "God is Love:" why do we go forth and run to the
heights of the heavens and the lowest parts of the earth, seeking Him
who is within us, if we wish to be with Him?
Footnotes
[677] Matt. xxii. 37-40
[678] Rom. viii. 28
[679] 1 Cor. viii. 3
[680] Rom. v. 5
[681] Gal. vi. 2
[682] Gal. v. 14
[683] Matt. vii. 12
[684] 1 John iv. 6
[685] Matt. xi. 28, 29
[686] Charity.--A.V.
[687] 1 Cor. xiii. 4
[688] 1 John iv. 8
[689] Abide with.--A.V.
[690] Wisd. iii. 9
Chapter 8.--That He Who Loves His Brother, Loves God; Because He Loves
Love Itself, Which is of God, and is God.
12. Let no one say, I do not know what I love. Let him love his
brother, and he will love the same love. For he knows the love with
which he loves, more than the brother whom he loves. So now he can
know God more than he knows his brother: clearly known more, because
more present; known more, because more within him; known more, because
more certain. Embrace the love of God, and by love embrace God. That
is love itself, which associates together all good angels and all the
servants of God by the bond of sanctity, and joins together us and
them mutually with ourselves, and joins us subordinately to Himself.
In proportion, therefore, as we are healed from the swelling of pride,
in such proportion are we more filled with love; and with what is he
full, who is full of love, except with God? Well, but you will say, I
see love, and, as far as I am able, I gaze upon it with my mind, and I
believe the Scripture, saying, that "God is love; and he that dwelleth
in love, dwelleth in God;" [691] but when I see love, I do not see in
it the Trinity. Nay, but thou dost see the Trinity if thou seest love.
But if I can I will put you in mind, that thou mayest see that thou
seest it; only let itself be present, that we may be moved by love to
something good. Since, when we love love, we love one who loves
something, and that on account of this very thing, that he does love
something; therefore what does love love, that love itself also may be
loved? For that is not love which loves nothing. But if it loves
itself it must love something, that it may love itself as love. For as
a word indicates something, and indicates also itself, but does not
indicate itself to be a word, unless it indicates that it does
indicate something; so love also loves indeed itself, but except it
love itself as loving something, it loves itself not as love. What
therefore does love love, except that which we love with love? But
this, to begin from that which is nearest to us, is our brother. And
listen how greatly the Apostle John commends brotherly love: "He that
loveth his brother abideth in the light, and there is none occasion of
stumbling in him." [692] It is manifest that he placed the perfection
of righteousness in the love of our brother; for he certainly is
perfect in whom "there is no occasion of stumbling." And yet he seems
to have passed by the love of God in silence; which he never would
have done, unless because he intends God to be understood in brotherly
love itself. For in this same epistle, a little further on, he says
most plainly thus: "Beloved, let us love one another: for love is of
God; and every one that loveth is born of God, and knoweth God. He
that loveth not, knoweth not God; for God is love." And this passage
declares sufficiently and plainly, that this same brotherly love
itself (for that is brotherly love by which we love each other) is set
forth by so great authority, not only to be from God, but also to be
God. When, therefore, we love our brother from love, we love our
brother from God; neither can it be that we do not love above all else
that same love by which we love our brother: whence it may be gathered
that these two commandments cannot exist unless interchangeably. For
since "God is love," he who loves love certainly loves God; but he
must needs love love, who loves his brother. And so a little after he
says, "For he that loveth not his brother whom he hath seen, how can
he love God whom he hath not seen"? [693] because the reason that he
does not see God is, that he does not love his brother. For he who
does not love his brother, abideth not in love; and he who abideth not
in love, abideth not in God, because God is love. Further, he who
abideth not in God, abideth not in light; for "God is light, and in
Him is no darkness at all." [694] He therefore who abideth not in
light, what wonder is it if he does not see light, that is, does not
see God, because he is in darkness? But he sees his brother with human
sight, with which God cannot be seen. But if he loved with spiritual
love him whom he sees with human sight, he would see God, who is love
itself, with the inner sight by which He can be seen. Therefore he who
does not love his brother whom he sees, how can he love God, whom on
that account he does not see, because God is love, which he has not
who does not love his brother? Neither let that further question
disturb us, how much of love we ought to spend upon our brother, and
how much upon God: incomparably more upon God than upon ourselves, but
upon our brother as much as upon ourselves; and we love ourselves so
much the more, the more we love God. Therefore we love God and our
neighbor from one and the same love; but we love God for the sake of
God, and ourselves and our neighbors for the sake of God.
Footnotes
[691] 1 John iv. 16
[692] 1 John ii. 10
[693] 1 John iv. 7, 8, 20
[694] 1 John i. 5
Chapter 9.--Our Love of the Righteous is Kindled from Love Itself of
the Unchangeable Form of Righteousness.
13. For why is it, pray, that we burn when we hear and read, "Behold,
now is the accepted time; behold, now is the day of salvation: giving
no offense in anything, that the ministry be not blamed: but in all
things approving ourselves as the ministers of God, in much patience,
in afflictions, in necessities, in distresses, in stripes, in
imprisonments, in tumults, in labors, in watchings, in fastings; by
pureness, by knowledge, by long-suffering, by kindness, by the Holy
Ghost, by love unfeigned, by the word of truth, by the power of God,
by the armor of righteousness on the right hand and on the left, by
honor and dishonor, by evil report and good report: as deceivers, and
yet true; as unknown, and yet well known; as dying, and, behold, we
live; as chastened, and not killed; as sorrowful, yet alway rejoicing;
as poor, yet making many rich; as having nothing, and yet possessing
all things?" [695] Why is it that we are inflamed with love of the
Apostle Paul, when we read these things, unless that we believe him so
to have lived? But we do not believe that the ministers of God ought
so to live because we have heard it from any one, but because we
behold it inwardly within ourselves, or rather above ourselves, in the
truth itself. Him, therefore, whom we believe to have so lived, we
love for that which we see. And except we loved above all else that
form which we discern as always steadfast and unchangeable, we should
not for that reason love him, because we hold fast in our belief that
his life, when he was living in the flesh, was adapted to, and in
harmony with, this form. But somehow we are stirred up the more to the
love of this form itself, through the belief by which we believe some
one to have so lived; and to the hope by which we no more at all
despair, that we, too, are able so to live; we who are men, from this
fact itself, that some men have so lived, so that we both desire this
more ardently, and pray for it more confidently. So both the love of
that form, according to which they are believed to have lived, makes
the life of these men themselves to be loved by us; and their life
thus believed stirs up a more burning love towards that same form; so
that the more ardently we love God, the more certainly and the more
calmly do we see Him, because we behold in God the unchangeable form
of righteousness, according to which we judge that man ought to live.
Therefore faith avails to the knowledge and to the love of God, not as
though of one altogether unknown, or altogether not loved; but so that
thereby He may be known more clearly, and loved more steadfastly.
Footnotes
[695] 2 Cor. vi. 2-10
Chapter 10.--There are Three Things in Love, as It Were a Trace of the
Trinity.
14. But what is love or charity, which divine Scripture so greatly
praises and proclaims, except the love of good? But love is of some
one that loves, and with love something is loved. Behold, then, there
are three things: he that loves, and that which is loved, and love.
What, then, is love, except a certain life which couples or seeks to
couple together some two things, namely, him that loves, and that
which is loved? And this is so even in outward and carnal loves. But
that we may drink in something more pure and clear, let us tread down
the flesh and ascend to the mind. What does the mind love in a friend
except the mind? There, then, also are three things: he that loves,
and that which is loved, and love. It remains to ascend also from
hence, and to seek those things which are above, as far as is given to
man. But here for a little while let our purpose rest, not that it may
think itself to have found already what it seeks; but just as usually
the place has first to be found where anything is to be sought, while
the thing itself is not yet found, but we have only found already
where to look for it; so let it suffice to have said thus much, that
we may have, as it were, the hinge of some starting-point, whence to
weave the rest of our discourse.
.
Book IX.
That a kind of trinity exists in man, who is the image of God, viz.
the mind, and the knowledge wherewith the mind knows itself, and the
love wherewith it loves both itself and its own knowledge; and these
three are shown to be mutually equal, and of one essence.
Chapter 1.--In What Way We Must Inquire Concerning the Trinity.
1. We certainly seek a trinity,--not any trinity, but that Trinity
which is God, and the true and supreme and only God. Let my hearers
then wait, for we are still seeking. And no one justly finds fault
with such a search, if at least he who seeks that which either to know
or to utter is most difficult, is steadfast in the faith. But
whosoever either sees or teaches better, finds fault quickly and
justly with any one who confidently affirms concerning it. "Seek God,"
he says, "and your heart shall live;" [696] and lest any one should
rashly rejoice that he has, as it were, apprehended it, "Seek," he
says, "His face evermore." [697] And the apostle: "If any man," he
says, "think that he knoweth anything, he knoweth nothing yet as he
ought to know. But if any man love God, the same is known of Him."
[698] He has not said, has known Him, which is dangerous presumption,
but "is known of Him." So also in another place, when he had said,
"But now after that ye have known God:" immediately correcting
himself, he says, "or rather are known of God." [699] And above all in
that other place, "Brethren," he says, "I count not myself to have
apprehended: but this one thing I do, forgetting those things which
are behind, and reaching forth unto those things which are before, I
press in purpose [700] toward the mark, for the prize of the high
calling of God in Christ Jesus. Let us therefore, as many as be
perfect, be thus minded." [701] Perfection in this life, he tells us,
is nothing else than to forget those things which are behind, and to
reach forth and press in purpose toward those things which are before.
For he that seeks has the safest purpose, [who seeks] until that is
taken hold of whither we are tending, and for which we are reaching
forth. But that is the right purpose which starts from faith. For a
certain faith is in some way the starting-point of knowledge; but a
certain knowledge will not be made perfect, except after this life,
when we shall see face to face. [702] Let us therefore be thus minded,
so as to know that the disposition to seek the truth is more safe than
that which presumes things unknown to be known. Let us therefore so
seek as if we should find, and so find as if we were about to seek.
For "when a man hath done, then he beginneth." [703] Let us doubt
without unbelief of things to be believed; let us affirm without
rashness of things to be understood: authority must be held fast in
the former, truth sought out in the latter. As regards this question,
then, let us believe that the Father, and the Son, and the Holy Spirit
is one God, the Creator and Ruler of the whole creature; and that the
Father is not the Son, nor the Holy Spirit either the Father or the
Son, but a trinity of persons mutually interrelated, and a unity of an
equal essence. And let us seek to understand this, praying for help
from Himself, whom we wish to understand; and as much as He grants,
desiring to explain what we understand with so much pious care and
anxiety, that even if in any case we say one thing for another, we may
at least say nothing unworthy. As, for the sake of example, if we say
anything concerning the Father that does not properly belong to the
Father, or does belong to the Son, or to the Holy Spirit, or to the
Trinity itself; and if anything of the Son which does not properly
suit with the Son, or at all events which does suit with the Father,
or with the Holy Spirit, or with the Trinity; or if, again, anything
concerning the Holy Spirit, which is not fitly a property of the Holy
Spirit, yet is not alien from the Father, or from the Son, or from the
one God the Trinity itself. Even as now our wish is to see whether the
Holy Spirit is properly that love which is most excellent which if He
is not, either the Father is love, or the Son, or the Trinity itself;
since we cannot withstand the most certain faith and weighty authority
of Scripture, saying, "God is love." [704] And yet we ought not to
deviate into profane error, so as to say anything of the Trinity which
does not suit the Creator, but rather the creature, or which is
feigned outright by mere empty thought.
Footnotes
[696] Ps. lxix. 32
[697] Ps. cv. 4
[698] 1 Cor. viii. 2
[699] Gal. iv. 19
[700] In purpose, om. in A.V.
[701] Phil. iii. 13-15
[702] 1 Cor. xiii. 12
[703] Ecclus. xviii. 7
[704] 1 John iv. 16
Chapter 2.--The Three Things Which are Found in Love Must Be
Considered. [705]
2. And this being so, let us direct our attention to those three
things which we fancy we have found. We are not yet speaking of
heavenly things, nor yet of God the Father, and Son, and Holy Spirit,
but of that inadequate image, which yet is an image, that is, man; for
our feeble mind perhaps can gaze upon this more familiarly and more
easily. Well then, when I, who make this inquiry, love anything, there
are three things concerned--myself, and that which I love, and love
itself. For I do not love love, except I love a lover; for there is no
love where nothing is loved. Therefore there are three things--he who
loves, and that which is loved, and love. But what if I love none
except myself? Will there not then be two things--that which I love,
and love? For he who loves and that which is loved are the same when
any one loves himself; just as to love and to be loved, in the same
way, is the very same thing when any one loves himself. Since the same
thing is said, when it is said, he loves himself, and he is loved by
himself. For in that case to love and to be loved are not two
different things: just as he who loves and he who is loved are not two
different persons. But yet, even so, love and what is loved are still
two things. For there is no love when any one loves himself, except
when love itself is loved. But it is one thing to love one's self,
another to love one's own love. For love is not loved, unless as
already loving something; since where nothing is loved there is no
love. Therefore there are two things when any one loves himself--love,
and that which is loved. For then he that loves and that which is
loved are one. Whence it seems that it does not follow that three
things are to be understood wherever love is. For let us put aside
from the inquiry all the other many things of which a man consists;
and in order that we may discover clearly what we are now seeking, as
far as in such a subject is possible, let us treat of the mind alone.
The mind, then, when it loves itself, discloses two things--mind and
love. But what is to love one's self, except to wish to help one's
self to the enjoyment of self? And when any one wishes himself to be
just as much as he is, then the will is on a par with the mind, and
the love is equal to him who loves. And if love is a substance, it is
certainly not body, but spirit; and the mind also is not body, but
spirit. Yet love and mind are not two spirits, but one spirit; nor yet
two essences, but one: and yet here are two things that are one, he
that loves and love; or, if you like so to put it, that which is loved
and love. And these two, indeed, are mutually said relatively. Since
he who loves is referred to love, and love to him who loves. For he
who loves, loves with some love, and love is the love of some one who
loves. But mind and spirit are not said relatively, but express
essence. For mind and spirit do not exist because the mind and spirit
of some particular man exists. For if we subtract the body from that
which is man, which is so called with the conjunction of body, the
mind and spirit remain. But if we subtract him that loves, then there
is no love; and if we subtract love, then there is no one that loves.
And therefore, in so far as they are mutually referred to one another,
they are two; but whereas they are spoken in respect to themselves,
each are spirit, and both together also are one spirit; and each are
mind, and both together one mind. Where, then, is the trinity? Let us
attend as much as we can, and let us invoke the everlasting light,
that He may illuminate our darkness, and that we may see in ourselves,
as much as we are permitted, the image of God.
Footnotes
[705] [Augustin here begins his discussion of some ternaries that are
found in the Finite, that illustrate the trinality of the Infinite.
Like all finite analogies, they fail at certain points. In the case
chosen--namely, the lover, the loved, and love--the first two are
substances, the last is not. The mind is a substance, but its activity
in loving is not. In chapter iv. 5, Augustin asserts that "love and
knowledge exist substantially, as the mind itself does." But no
psychology, ancient or modern, has ever maintained that the agencies
of a spiritual entity or substance are themselves spiritual entity or
substances. The activities of the human mind in cognizing, loving,
etc., are only its energizing, not its substance. The ambiguity of the
Latin contributes to this error. The mind and its loving, and also the
mind and its cognizing, are denominated "duo quædam" the mind, love,
and knowledge, are denominated "tria quædem." By bringing the mind and
its love and knowledge under the one term "quædam," and then giving
the meaning of "substance" to "thing," in "something," the result
follows that all three are alike and equally "substantial." This
analogy taken from the mind and its activities illustrates the
trinality of the Divine essence, but fails to illustrate the
substantiality of the three persons. The three Divine persons are not
the Divine essence together with two of its activities (such, e.g., as
creation and redemption), but the essence in three modes, or "forms,"
as St. Paul denominates them in Phil. iii. 6 If Augustin could prove
his assertion that the activities of the human spirit in knowing and
loving are strictly "substantial," then this ternary would illustrate
not only the trinality of the essence, but the essentiality and
objectivity of the persons. The fact which he mentions, that knowledge
and love are inseparable from the knowing and loving mind, does not
prove their equal substantiality with the mind.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 3.--The Image of the Trinity in the Mind of Man Who Knows
Himself and Loves Himself. The Mind Knows Itself Through Itself.
3. For the mind cannot love itself, except also it know itself; for
how can it love what it does not know? Or if any body says that the
mind, from either general or special knowledge, believes itself of
such a character as it has by experience found others to be and
therefore loves itself, he speaks most foolishly. For whence does a
mind know another mind, if it does not know itself? For the mind does
not know other minds and not know itself, as the eye of the body sees
other eyes and does not see itself; for we see bodies through the eyes
of the body, because, unless we are looking into a mirror, we cannot
refract and reflect the rays into themselves which shine forth through
those eyes, and touch whatever we discern,--a subject, indeed, which
is treated of most subtlely and obscurely, until it be clearly
demonstrated whether the fact be so, or whether it be not. But
whatever is the nature of the power by which we discern through the
eyes, certainly, whether it be rays or anything else, we cannot
discern with the eyes that power itself; but we inquire into it with
the mind, and if possible, understand even this with the mind. As the
mind, then, itself gathers the knowledge of corporeal things through
the senses of the body, so of incorporeal things through itself.
Therefore it knows itself also through itself, since it is
incorporeal; for if it does not know itself, it does not love itself.
Chapter 4.--The Three are One, and Also Equal, Viz The Mind Itself,
and the Love, and the Knowledge of It. That the Same Three Exist
Substantially, and are Predicated Relatively. That the Same Three are
Inseparable. That the Same Three are Not Joined and Commingled Like
Parts, But that They are of One Essence, and are Relatives.
4. But as there are two things (duo quædam), the mind and the love of
it, when it loves itself; so there are two things, the mind and the
knowledge of it, when it knows itself. Therefore the mind itself, and
the love of it, and the knowledge of it, are three things (tria
quædam), and these three are one; and when they are perfect they are
equal. For if one loves himself less than as he is,--as for example,
suppose that the mind of a man only loves itself as much as the body
of a man ought to be loved, whereas the mind is more than the
body,--then it is in fault, and its love is not perfect. Again, if it
loves itself more than as it is,--as if, for instance, it loves itself
as much as God is to be loved, whereas the mind is incomparably less
than God,--here also it is exceedingly in fault, and its love of self
is not perfect. But it is in fault more perversely and wrongly still,
when it loves the body as much as God is to be loved. Also, if
knowledge is less than that thing which is known, and which can be
fully known, then knowledge is not perfect; but if it is greater, then
the nature which knows is above that which is known, as the knowledge
of the body is greater than the body itself, which is known by that
knowledge. For knowledge is a kind of life in the reason of the
knower, but the body is not life; and any life is greater than any
body, not in bulk, but in power. But when the mind knows itself, its
own knowledge does not rise above itself, because itself knows, and
itself is known. When, therefore, it knows itself entirely, and no
other thing with itself, then its knowledge is equal to itself;
because its knowledge is not from another nature, since it knows
itself. And when it perceives itself entirely, and nothing more, then
it is neither less nor greater. We said therefore rightly, that these
three things, [mind, love, and knowledge], when they are perfect, are
by consequence equal.
5. Similar reasoning suggests to us, if indeed we can any way
understand the matter, that these things [i.e. love and knowledge]
exist in the soul, and that, being as it were involved in it, they are
so evolved from it as to be perceived and reckoned up substantially,
or, so to say, essentially. Not as though in a subject; as color, or
shape, or any other quality or quantity, are in the body. For anything
of this [material] kind does not go beyond the subject in which it is;
for the color or shape of this particular body cannot be also those of
another body. But the mind can also love something besides itself,
with that love with which it loves itself. And further, the mind does
not know itself only, but also many other things. Wherefore love and
knowledge are not contained in the mind as in a subject, but these
also exist substantially, as the mind itself does; because, even if
they are mutually predicated relatively, yet they exist each severally
in their own substance. Nor are they so mutually predicated relatively
as color and the colored subject are; so that color is in the colored
subject, but has not any proper substance in itself, since colored
body is a substance, but color is in a substance; but as two friends
are also two men, which are substances, while they are said to be men
not relatively, but friends relatively.
6. But, further, although one who loves or one who knows is a
substance, and knowledge is a substance, and love is a substance, but
he that loves and love, or, he that knows and knowledge, are spoken of
relatively to each other, as are friends: yet mind or spirit are not
relatives, as neither are men relatives: nevertheless he that loves
and love, or he that knows and knowledge, cannot exist separately from
each other, as men can that are friends. Although it would seem that
friends, too, can be separated in body, not in mind, in as far as they
are friends: nay, it can even happen that a friend may even also begin
to hate a friend and on this account cease to be a friend while the
other does not know it, and still loves him. But if the love with
which the mind loves itself ceases to be, then the mind also will at
the same time cease to love. Likewise, if the knowledge by which the
mind knows itself ceases to be, then the mind will also at the same
time cease to know itself. Just as the head of anything that has a
head is certainly a head, and they are predicated relatively to each
other, although they are also substances: for both a head is a body,
and so is that which has a head; and if there be no head, then neither
will there be that which has a head. Only these things can be
separated from each other by cutting off, those cannot.
7. And even if there are some bodies which cannot be wholly separated
and divided, yet they would not be bodies unless they consisted of
their own proper parts. A part then is predicated relatively to a
whole, since every part is a part of some whole, and a whole is a
whole by having all its parts. But since both part and whole are
bodies, these things are not only predicated relatively, but exist
also substantially. Perhaps, then, the mind is a whole, and the love
with which it loves itself, and the knowledge with which it knows
itself, are as it were its parts, of which two parts that whole
consists. Or are there three equal parts which make up the one whole?
But no part embraces the whole, of which it is a part; whereas, when
the mind knows itself as a whole, that is, knows itself perfectly,
then the knowledge of it extends through the whole of it; and when it
loves itself perfectly, then it loves itself as a whole, and the love
of it extends through the whole of it. Is it, then, as one drink is
made from wine and water and honey, and each single part extends
through the whole, and yet they are three things (for there is no part
of the drink which does not contain these three things; for they are
not joined as if they were water and oil, but are entirely commingled:
and they are all substances, and the whole of that liquor which is
composed of the three is one substance),--is it, I say, in some such
way as this we are to think these three to be together, mind, love,
and knowledge? But water, wine, and honey are not of one substance,
although one substance results in the drink made from the commingling
of them. And I cannot see how those other three are not of the same
substance, since the mind itself loves itself, and itself knows
itself; and these three so exist, as that the mind is neither loved
nor known by any other thing at all. These three, therefore, must
needs be of one and the same essence; and for that reason, if they
were confounded together as it were by a commingling, they could not
be in any way three, neither could they be mutually referred to each
other. Just as if you were to make from one and the same gold three
similar rings, although connected with each other, they are mutually
referred to each other, because they are similar. For everything
similar is similar to something, and there is a trinity of rings, and
one gold. But if they are blended with each other, and each mingled
with the other through the whole of their own bulk, then that trinity
will fall through, and it will not exist at all; and not only will it
be called one gold, as it was called in the case of those three rings,
but now it will not be called three things of gold at all.
Chapter 5.--That These Three are Several in Themselves, and Mutually
All in All.
8. But in these three, when the mind knows itself and loves itself,
there remains a trinity: mind, love, knowledge; and this trinity is
not confounded together by any commingling: although they are each
severally in themselves and mutually all in all, or each severally in
each two, or each two in each. Therefore all are in all. For certainly
the mind is in itself, since it is called mind in respect to itself:
although it is said to be knowing, or known, or knowable, relatively
to its own knowledge; and although also as loving, and loved, or
lovable, it is referred to love, by which it loves itself. And
knowledge, although it is referred to the mind that knows or is known,
nevertheless is also predicated both as known and knowing in respect
to itself: for the knowledge by which the mind knows itself is not
unknown to itself. And although love is referred to the mind that
loves, whose love it is; nevertheless it is also love in respect to
itself, so as to exist also in itself: since love too is loved, yet
cannot be loved with anything except with love, that is with itself.
So these things are severally in themselves. But so are they in each
other; because both the mind that loves is in love, and love is in the
knowledge of him that loves, and knowledge is in the mind that knows.
And each severally is in like manner in each two, because the mind
which knows and loves itself, is in its own love and knowledge: and
the love of the mind that loves and knows itself, is in the mind and
in its knowledge: and the knowledge of the mind that knows and loves
itself is in the mind and in its love, because it loves itself that
knows, and knows itself that loves. And hence also each two is in each
severally, since the mind which knows and loves itself, is together
with its own knowledge in love, and together with its own love in
knowledge; and love too itself and knowledge are together in the mind,
which loves and knows itself. But in what way all are in all, we have
already shown above; since the mind loves itself as a whole, and knows
itself as a whole, and knows its own love wholly, and loves its own
knowledge wholly, when these three things are perfect in respect to
themselves. Therefore these three things are marvellously inseparable
from each other, and yet each of them is severally a substance, and
all together are one substance or essence, whilst they are mutually
predicated relatively. [706]
Footnotes
[706] [Augustin here illustrates, by the ternary of mind, love, and
knowledge, what the Greek Trinitarians denominate the perichoresis of
the divine essence. By the figure of a circulation, they describe the
eternal inbeing and indwelling of one person in another. This is
founded on John xiv. 10, 11; xvii. 21, 23. "Believest thou not that I
am in the Father, and the Father in Me? I pray that they all may be
one, as thou Father art in Me, and I in Thee." Athanasius (Oratio,
iii. 21) remarks that Christ here prays that the disciples "may
imitate the trinitarian unity of essence, in their unity of
affection." Had it been possible for the disciples to be in the
essence of the Father as the Son is, he would have prayed that they
all may be "one in Thee," instead of "one in Us." The Platonists,
also, employed this figure of circulatory movement, to explain the
self-reflecting and self-communing nature of the human mind. "It is
not possible for us to know what our souls are, but only by their
kineseis kuklikai, their circular and reflex motions and converse with
themselves, which only can steal from them their own secrets." J.
Smith: Immortality of the Soul, Ch. ii. Augustin's illustration,
however, is imperfect, because "the three things" which circulate are
not "each of them severally a substance." Only one of them, namely,
the mind, is a substance.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 6.--There is One Knowledge of the Thing in the Thing Itself,
and Another in Eternal Truth Itself. That Corporeal Things, Too, are
to Be Judged the Rules of Eternal Truth.
9. But when the human mind knows itself and loves itself, it does not
know and love anything unchangeable: and each individual man declares
his own particular mind by one manner of speech, when he considers
what takes place in himself; but defines the human mind abstractly by
special or general knowledge. And so, when he speaks to me of his own
individual mind, as to whether he understands this or that, or does
not understand it, or whether he wishes or does not wish this or that,
I believe; but when he speaks the truth of the mind of man generally
or specially, I recognize and approve. Whence it is manifest, that
each sees a thing in himself, in such way that another person may
believe what he says of it, yet may not see it; but another [sees a
thing] in the truth itself, in such way that another person also can
gaze upon it; of which the former undergoes changes at successive
times, the latter consists in an unchangeable eternity. For we do not
gather a generic or specific knowledge of the human mind by means of
resemblance by seeing many minds with the eyes of the body: but we
gaze upon indestructible truth, from which to define perfectly, as far
as we can, not of what sort is the mind of any one particular man, but
of what sort it ought to be upon the eternal plan.
10. Whence also, even in the case of the images of things corporeal
which are drawn in through the bodily sense, and in some way infused
into the memory, from which also those things which have not been seen
are thought under a fancied image, whether otherwise than they really
are, or even perchance as they are;--even here too, we are proved
either to accept or reject, within ourselves, by other rules which
remain altogether unchangeable above our mind, when we approve or
reject anything rightly. For both when I recall the walls of Carthage
which I have seen, and imagine to myself the walls of Alexandria which
I have not seen, and, in preferring this to that among forms which in
both cases are imaginary, make that preference upon grounds of reason;
the judgment of truth from above is still strong and clear, and rests
firmly upon the utterly indestructible rules of its own right; and if
it is covered as it were by cloudiness of corporeal images, yet is not
wrapt up and confounded in them.
11. But it makes a difference, whether, under that or in that
darkness, I am shut off as it were from the clear heaven; or whether
(as usually happens on lofty mountains), enjoying the free air between
both, I at once look up above to the calmest light, and down below
upon the densest clouds. For whence is the ardor of brotherly love
kindled in me, when I hear that some man has borne bitter torments for
the excellence and steadfastness of faith? And if that man is shown to
me with the finger, I am eager to join myself to him, to become
acquainted with him, to bind him to myself in friendship. And
accordingly, if opportunity offers, I draw near, I address him, I
converse with him, I express my goodwill towards him in what words I
can, and wish that in him too in turn should be brought to pass and
expressed goodwill towards me; and I endeavor after a spiritual
embrace in the way of belief, since I cannot search out so quickly and
discern altogether his innermost heart. I love therefore the faithful
and courageous man with a pure and genuine love. But if he were to
confess to me in the course of conversation, or were through
unguardedness to show in any way, that either he believes something
unseemly of God, and desires also something carnal in Him, and that he
bore these torments on behalf of such an error, or from the desire of
money for which he hoped, or from empty greediness of human praise:
immediately it follows that the love with which I was borne towards
him, displeased, and as it were repelled, and taken away from an
unworthy man, remains in that form, after which, believing him such as
I did, I had loved him; unless perhaps I have come to love him to this
end, that he may become such, while I have found him not to be such in
fact. And in that man, too, nothing is changed: although it can be
changed, so that he may become that which I had believed him to be
already. But in my mind there certainly is something changed, viz.,
the estimate I had formed of him, which was before of one sort, and
now is of another: and the same love, at the bidding from above of
unchangeable righteousness, is turned aside from the purpose of
enjoying, to the purpose of taking counsel. But the form itself of
unshaken and stable truth, wherein I should have enjoyed the fruition
of the man, believing him to be good, and wherein likewise I take
counsel that he may be good, sheds in an immoveable eternity the same
light of incorruptible and most sound reason, both upon the sight of
my mind, and upon that cloud of images, which I discern from above,
when I think of the same man whom I had seen. Again, when I call back
to my mind some arch, turned beautifully and symmetrically, which, let
us say, I saw at Carthage; a certain reality that had been made known
to the mind through the eyes, and transferred to the memory, causes
the imaginary view. But I behold in my mind yet another thing,
according to which that work of art pleases me; and whence also, if it
displeased me, I should correct it. We judge therefore of those
particular things according to that [form of eternal truth], and
discern that form by the intuition of the rational mind. But those
things themselves we either touch if present by the bodily sense, or
if absent remember their images as fixed in our memory, or picture, in
the way of likeness to them, such things as we ourselves also, if we
wished and were able, would laboriously build up: figuring in the mind
after one fashion the images of bodies, or seeing bodies through the
body; but after another, grasping by simple intelligence what is above
the eye of the mind, viz., the reasons and the unspeakably beautiful
skill of such forms.
Chapter 7.--We Conceive and Beget the Word Within, from the Things We
Have Beheld in the Eternal Truth. The Word, Whether of the Creature or
of the Creator, is Conceived by Love.
12. We behold, then, by the sight of the mind, in that eternal truth
from which all things temporal are made, the form according to which
we are, and according to which we do anything by true and right
reason, either in ourselves, or in things corporeal; and we have the
true knowledge of things, thence conceived, as it were as a word
within us, and by speaking we beget it from within; nor by being born
does it depart from us. And when we speak to others, we apply to the
word, remaining within us, the ministry of the voice or of some bodily
sign, that by some kind of sensible remembrance some similar thing may
be wrought also in the mind of him that hears,--similar, I say, to
that which does not depart from the mind of him that speaks. We do
nothing, therefore, through the members of the body in our words and
actions, by which the behavior of men is either approved or blamed,
which we do not anticipate by a word uttered within ourselves. For no
one willingly does anything, which he has not first said in his heart.
13. And this word is conceived by love, either of the creature or of
the Creator, that is, either of changeable nature or of unchangeable
truth. [707]
Footnotes
[707] [The inward production of a thought in the finite essence of the
human spirit which is expressed outwardly in a spoken word, is
analogous to the eternal generation of the Eternal Wisdom in the
infinite essence of God expressed in the Eternal Word. Both are alike,
in that something spiritual issues from something spiritual, without
division or diminution of substance. But a thought of the human mind
is not an objective thing or substance; while the Eternal Word
is.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 8.--In What Desire and Love Differ.
[Conceived] therefore, either by desire or by love: not that the
creature ought not to be loved; but if that love [of the creature] is
referred to the Creator, then it will not be desire (cupiditas), but
love (charitas). For it is desire when the creature is loved for
itself. And then it does not help a man through making use of it, but
corrupts him in the enjoying it. When, therefore, the creature is
either equal to us or inferior, we must use the inferior in order to
God, but we must enjoy the equal duly in God. For as thou oughtest to
enjoy thyself, not in thyself, but in Him who made thee, so also him
whom thou lovest as thyself. Let us enjoy, therefore, both ourselves
and our brethren in the Lord; and hence let us not dare to yield, and
as it were to relax, ourselves to ourselves in the direction
downwards. Now a word is born, when, being thought out, it pleases us
either to the effect of sinning, or to that of doing right. Therefore
love, as it were a mean, conjoins our word and the mind from which it
is conceived, and without any confusion binds itself as a third with
them, in an incorporeal embrace.
Chapter 9.--In the Love of Spiritual Things the Word Born is the Same
as the Word Conceived. It is Otherwise in the Love of Carnal Things.
14. But the word conceived and the word born are the very same when
the will finds rest in knowledge itself, as is the case in the love of
spiritual things. For instance, he who knows righteousness perfectly,
and loves it perfectly, is already righteous; even if no necessity
exist of working according to it outwardly through the members of the
body. But in the love of carnal and temporal things, as in the
offspring of animals, the conception of the word is one thing, the
bringing forth another. For here what is conceived by desiring is born
by attaining. Since it does not suffice to avarice to know and to love
gold, except it also have it; nor to know and love to eat, or to lie
with any one, unless also one does it; nor to know and love honors and
power, unless they actually come to pass. Nay, all these things, even
if obtained, do not suffice. "Whosoever drinketh of this water," He
says, "shall thirst again." [708] And so also the Psalmist, "He hath
conceived pain and brought forth iniquity." [709] And he speaks of
pain or labor as conceived, when those things are conceived which it
is not sufficient to know and will, and when the mind burns and grows
sick with want, until it arrives at those things, and, as it were,
brings them forth. Whence in the Latin language we have the word
"parta" used elegantly for both "reperta" and "comperta," which words
sound as if derived from bringing forth. [710] Since "lust, when it
hath conceived, bringeth forth sin." [711] Wherefore the Lord
proclaims, "Come unto me all ye that labor and are heavy laden;" [712]
and in another place "Woe unto them that are with child, and to them
that give suck, in those days!" [713] And when therefore He referred
all either right actions or sins to the bringing forth of the word,
"By thy mouth," [714] He says, "thou shalt be justified, and by thy
mouth [715] thou shalt be condemned," [716] intending thereby not the
visible mouth, but that which is within and invisible, of the thought
and of the heart.
Footnotes
[708] John iv. 13
[709] Ps. vii. 14
[710] Partus
[711] Jas. i. 15
[712] Matt. xi. 28
[713] Matt. xxiv. 19
[714] Words.
[715] Words.--A.V.
[716] Matt. xii. 37
Chapter 10.--Whether Only Knowledge that is Loved is the Word of the
Mind.
15. It is rightly asked then, whether all knowledge is a word, or only
knowledge that is loved. For we also know the things which we hate;
but what we do not like, cannot be said to be either conceived or
brought forth by the mind. For not all things which in anyway touch
it, are conceived by it; but some only reach the point of being known,
but yet are not spoken as words, as for instance those of which we
speak now. For those are called words in one way, which occupy spaces
of time by their syllables, whether they are pronounced or only
thought; and in another way, all that is known is called a word
imprinted on the mind, as long as it can be brought forth from the
memory and defined, even though we dislike the thing itself; and in
another way still, when we like that which is conceived in the mind.
And that which the apostle says, must be taken according to this last
kind of word, "No man can say that Jesus is the Lord, but by the Holy
Ghost;" [717] since those also say this, but according to another
meaning of the term "word," of whom the Lord Himself says, "Not every
one that saith unto me, Lord, Lord, shall enter into the kingdom of
heaven." [718] Nay, even in the case of things which we hate, when we
rightly dislike and rightly censure them, we approve and like the
censure bestowed upon them, and it becomes a word. Nor is it the
knowledge of vices that displeases us, but the vices themselves. For I
like to know and define what intemperance is; and this is its word.
Just as there are known faults in art, and the knowledge of them is
rightly approved, when a connoisseur discerns the species or the
privation of excellence, as to affirm and deny that it is or that it
is not; yet to be without excellence and to fall away into fault, is
worthy of condemnation. And to define intemperance, and to say its
word, belongs to the art of morals; but to be intemperate belongs to
that which that art censures. Just as to know and define what a
solecism is, belongs to the art of speaking; but to be guilty of one,
is a fault which the same art reprehends. A word, then, which is the
point we wish now to discern and intimate, is knowledge together with
love. Whenever, then, the mind knows and loves itself, its word is
joined to it by love. And since it loves knowledge and knows love,
both the word is in love and love is in the word, and both are in him
who loves and speaks. [719]
Footnotes
[717] 1 Cor. xii. 3
[718] Matt. vii. 21
[719] [The meaning of this obscure chapter seems to be, that only what
the mind is pleased with, is the real expression and index of the
mind--its true "word." The true nature of the mind is revealed in its
sympathies. But this requires some qualification. For in the case of
contrary qualities, like right and wrong, beauty and ugliness, the
real nature of the mind is seen also in its antipathy as well as in
its sympathy; in its hatred of wrong as well as in its love of right.
Each alike is a true index of the mind, because each really implies
the other.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 11.--That the Image or Begotten Word of the Mind that Knows
Itself is Equal to the Mind Itself.
16. But all knowledge according to species is like the thing which it
knows. For there is another knowledge according to privation,
according to which we speak a word only when we condemn. And this
condemnation of a privation is equivalent to praise of the species,
and so is approved. The mind, then, contains some likeness to a known
species, whether when liking that species or when disliking its
privation. And hence, in so far as we know God, we are like Him, but
not like to the point of equality, since we do not know Him to the
extent of His own being. And as, when we speak of bodies by means of
the bodily sense, there arises in our mind some likeness of them,
which is a phantasm of the memory; for the bodies themselves are not
at all in the mind, when we think them, but only the likenesses of
those bodies; therefore, when we approve the latter for the former, we
err, for the approving of one thing for another is an error; yet the
image of the body in the mind is a thing of a better sort than the
species of the body itself, inasmuch as the former is in a better
nature, viz. in a living substance, as the mind is: so when we know
God, although we are made better than we were before we knew Him, and
above all when the same knowledge being also liked and worthily loved
becomes a word, and so that knowledge becomes a kind of likeness of
God; yet that knowledge is of a lower kind, since it is in a lower
nature; for the mind is creature, but God is Creator. And from this it
may be inferred, that when the mind knows and approves itself, this
same knowledge is in such way its word, as that it is altogether on a
par and equal with it, and the same; because it is neither the
knowledge of a lower essence, as of the body, nor of a higher, as of
God. And whereas knowledge bears a likeness to that which it knows,
that is, of which it is the knowledge; in this case it has perfect and
equal likeness, when the mind itself, which knows, is known. And so it
is both image and word; because it is uttered concerning that mind to
which it is equalled in knowing, and that which is begotten is equal
to the begetter.
Chapter 12.--Why Love is Not the Offspring of the Mind, as Knowledge
is So. The Solution of the Question. The Mind with the Knowledge of
Itself and the Love of Itself is the Image of the Trinity.
17. What then is love? Will it not be an image? Will it not be a word?
Will it not be begotten? For why does the mind beget its knowledge
when it knows itself, and not beget its love when it loves itself? For
if it is the cause of its own knowing, for the reason that it is
knowable, it is also the cause of its own love because it is lovable.
It is hard, then, to say why it does not beget both. For there is a
further question also respecting the supreme Trinity itself, the
omnipotent God the Creator, after whose image man is made, which
troubles men, whom the truth of God invites to the faith by human
speech; viz. why the Holy Spirit is not also to be either believed or
understood to be begotten by God the Father, so that He also may be
called a Son. And this question we are endeavoring in some way to
investigate in the human mind, in order that from a lower image, in
which our own nature itself as it were answers, upon being questioned,
in a way more familiar to ourselves, we may be able to direct a more
practised mental vision from the enlightened creature to the
unchangeable light; assuming, however, that the truth itself has
persuaded us, that as no Christian doubts the Word of God to be the
Son, so that the Holy Spirit is love. Let us return, then, to a more
careful questioning and consideration upon this subject of that image
which is the creature, that is, of the rational mind; wherein the
knowledge of some things coming into existence in time, but which did
not exist before, and the love of some things which were not loved
before, opens to us more clearly what to say: because to speech also
itself, which must be disposed in time, that thing is easier of
explanation which is comprehended in the order of time.
18. First, therefore, it is clear that a thing may possibly be
knowable, that is, such as can be known, and yet that it may be
unknown; but that it is not possible for that to be known which is not
knowable. Wherefore it must be clearly held that everything whatsoever
that we know begets at the same time in us the knowledge of itself;
for knowledge is brought forth from both, from the knower and from the
thing known. When, therefore, the mind knows itself, it alone is the
parent of its own knowledge; for it is itself both the thing known and
the knower of it. But it was knowable to itself also before it knew
itself, only the knowledge of itself was not in itself so long as it
did not know itself. In knowing itself, then, it begets a knowledge of
itself equal to itself; since it does not know itself as less than
itself is, nor is its knowledge the knowledge of the essence of some
one else, not only because itself knows, but also because it knows
itself, as we have said above. What then is to be said of love; why,
when the mind loves itself, it should not seem also to have begotten
the love of itself? For it was lovable to itself even before it loved
itself since it could love itself; just as it was knowable to itself
even before it knew itself, since it could know itself. For if it were
not knowable to itself, it never could have known itself; and so, if
it were not lovable to itself, it never could have loved itself. Why
therefore may it not be said by loving itself to have begotten its own
love, as by knowing itself it has begotten its own knowledge? Is it
because it is thereby indeed plainly shown that this is the principle
of love, whence it proceeds? for it proceeds from the mind itself,
which is lovable to itself before it loves itself, and so is the
principle of its own love by which it loves itself: but that this love
is not therefore rightly said to be begotten by the mind, as is the
knowledge of itself by which the mind knows itself, because in the
case of knowledge the thing has been found already, which is what we
call brought forth or discovered; [720] and this is commonly preceded
by an inquiry such as to find rest when that end is attained. For
inquiry is the desire of finding, or, what is the same thing, of
discovering. [721] But those things which are discovered are as it
were brought forth, whence they are like offspring; but wherein,
except in the case itself of knowledge? For in that case they are as
it were uttered and fashioned. For although the things existed already
which we found by seeking, yet the knowledge of them did not exist,
which knowledge we regard as an offspring that is born. Further, the
desire (appetitus) which there is in seeking proceeds from him who
seeks, and is in some way in suspense, and does not rest in the end
whither it is directed, except that which is sought be found and
conjoined with him who seeks. And this desire, that is,
inquiry,--although it does not seem to be love, by which that which is
known is loved, for in this case we are still striving to know,--yet
it is something of the same kind. For it can be called will
(voluntas),since every one who seeks wills (vult) to find; and if that
is sought which belongs to knowledge, every one who seeks wills to
know. But if he wills ardently and earnestly, he is said to study
(studere): a word that is most commonly employed in the case of
pursuing and obtaining any branches of learning. Therefore, the
bringing forth of the mind is preceded by some desire, by which,
through seeking and finding what we wish to know, the offspring, viz.
knowledge itself, is born. And for this reason, that desire by which
knowledge is conceived and brought forth, cannot rightly be called the
bringing forth and the offspring; and the same desire which led us to
long for the knowing of the thing, becomes the love of the thing when
known, while it holds and embraces its accepted offspring, that is,
knowledge, and unites it to its begetter. And so there is a kind of
image of the Trinity in the mind itself, and the knowledge of it,
which is its offspring and its word concerning itself, and love as a
third, and these three are one, and one substance. [722] Neither is
the offspring less, since the mind knows itself according to the
measure of its own being; nor is the love less, since it loves itself
according to the measure both of its own knowledge and of its own
being.
Footnotes
[720] "Partum" or "repertum."
[721] "Reperiendi."
[722] [It is not these three together that constitute the one
substance. The mind alone is the substance--the knowledge and the love
being only two activities of it. When the mind is not cognizing or
loving, it is still an entire mind. As previously remarked in the
annotation on IX. ii. this ternary will completely illustrate a
trinality of a certain kind, but not that of the Trinity; in which the
"tria quædam" are three subsistences, each of which is so substantial
as to be the subject of attributes, and to be able to employ them. The
human mind is substantial enough to possess and employ the attributes
of knowledge and love. We say that the mind knows and loves. But an
activity of the mind is not substantial enough to possess and employ
the attributes of knowledge and love. We cannot say that the loving
loves; or the loving knows; or the knowing loves, etc.--W.G.T.S.]
.
Book X.
In which there is shown to be another trinity in the mind of man, and
one that appears much more evidently, viz. in his memory,
understanding, and will.
Chapter 1.--The Love of the Studious Mind, that Is, of One Desirous to
Know, is Not the Love of a Thing Which It Does Not Know.
1. Let us now proceed, then, in due order, with a more exact purpose,
to explain this same point more thoroughly. And first, since no one
can love at all a thing of which he is wholly ignorant, we must
carefully consider of what sort is the love of those who are studious,
that is, of those who do not already know, but are still desiring to
know any branch of learning. Now certainly, in those things whereof
the word study is not commonly used, love often arises from hearsay,
when the reputation of anything for beauty inflames the mind to the
seeing and enjoying it; since the mind knows generically wherein
consist the beauties of corporeal things, from having seen them very
frequently, and since there exists within a faculty of approving that
which outwardly is longed for. And when this happens, the love that is
called forth is not of a thing wholly unknown, since its genus is thus
known. But when we love a good man whose face we never saw, we love
him from the knowledge of his virtues, which virtues we know
[abstractly] in the truth itself. But in the case of learning, it is
for the most part the authority of others who praise and commend it
that kindles our love of it; although nevertheless we could not burn
with any zeal at all for the study of it, unless we had already in our
mind at least a slight impression of the knowledge of each kind of
learning. For who, for instance, would devote any care and labor to
the learning of rhetoric, unless he knew before that it was the
science of speaking? Sometimes, again, we marvel at the results of
learning itself, which we have heard of or experienced; and hence burn
to obtain, by learning, the power of attaining these results. Just as
if it were said to one who did not know his letters, that there is a
kind of learning which enables a man to send words, wrought with the
hand in silence, to one who is ever so far absent, for him in turn to
whom they are sent to gather these words, not with his ears, but with
his eyes; and if the man were to see the thing actually done, is not
that man, since he desires to know how he can do this thing,
altogether moved to study with a view to the result which he already
knows and holds? So it is that the studious zeal of those who learn is
kindled: for that of which any one is utterly ignorant, he can in no
way love.
2. So also, if any one hear an unknown sign, as, for instance, the
sound of some word of which he does not know the signification, he
desires to know what it is; that is, he desires to know what thing it
is which it is agreed shall be brought to mind by that sound: as if he
heard the word temetum [723] uttered, and not knowing, should ask what
it is. He must then know already that it is a sign, i.e. that the word
is not an empty sound, but that something is signified by it; for in
other respects this trisyllabic word is known to him already, and has
already impressed its articulate form upon his mind through the sense
of hearing. And then what more is to be required in him, that he may
go on to a greater knowledge of that of which all the letters and all
the spaces of its several sounds are already known, unless that it
shall at the same time have become known to him that it is a sign, and
shall have also moved him with the desire of knowing of what it is the
sign? The more, then, the thing is known, yet not fully known, the
more the mind desires to know concerning it what remains to be known.
For if he knew it to be only such and such a spoken word, and did not
know that it was the sign of something, he would seek nothing further,
since the sensible thing is already perceived as far as it can be by
the sense. But because he knows it to be not only a spoken word, but
also a sign, he wishes to know it perfectly; and no sign is known
perfectly, except it be known of what it is the sign. He then who with
ardent carefulness seeks to know this, and inflamed by studious zeal
perseveres in the search; can such an one be said to be without love?
What then does he love? For certainly nothing can be loved unless it
is known. For that man does not love those three syllables which he
knows already. But if he loves this in them, that he knows them to
signify something, this is not the point now in question, for it is
not this which he seeks to know. But we are now asking what it is he
loves, in that which he is desirous to know, but which certainly he
does not yet know; and we are therefore wondering why he loves, since
we know most assuredly that nothing can be loved unless it be known.
What then does he love, except that he knows and perceives in the
reason of things what excellence there is in learning, in which the
knowledge of all signs is contained; and what benefit there is in the
being skilled in these, since by them human fellowship mutually
communicates its own perceptions, lest the assemblies of men should be
actually worse than utter solitude, if they were not to mingle their
thoughts by conversing together? The soul, then, discerns this fitting
and serviceable species, and knows it, and loves it; and he who seeks
the meaning of any words of which he is ignorant, studies to render
that species perfect in himself as much as he can: for it is one thing
to behold it in the light of truth, another to desire it as within his
own capacity. For he beholds in the light of truth how great and how
good a thing it is to understand and to speak all tongues of all
nations, and so to hear no tongue and to be heard by none as from a
foreigner. The beauty, then, of this knowledge is already discerned by
thought, and the thing being known is loved; and that thing is so
regarded, and so stimulates the studious zeal of learners, that they
are moved with respect to it, and desire it eagerly in all the labor
which they spend upon the attainment of such a capacity, in order that
they may also embrace in practice that which they know beforehand by
reason. And so every one, the nearer he approaches that capacity in
hope, the more fervently desires it with love; for those branches of
learning are studied the more eagerly, which men do not despair of
being able to attain; for when any one entertains no hope of attaining
his end, then he either loves lukewarmly or does not love at all,
howsoever he may see the excellence of it. Accordingly, because the
knowledge of all languages is almost universally felt to be hopeless,
every one studies most to know that of his own nation; but if he feels
that he is not sufficient even to comprehend this perfectly, yet no
one is so indolent in this knowledge as not to wish to know, when he
hears an unknown word, what it is, and to seek and learn it if he can.
And while he is seeking it, certainly he has a studious zeal of
learning, and seems to love a thing he does not know; but the case is
really otherwise. For that species touches the mind, which the mind
knows and thinks, wherein the fitness is clearly visible which accrues
from the associating of minds with one another, in the hearing and
returning of known and spoken words. And this species kindles studious
zeal in him who seeks what indeed he knows not, but gazes upon and
loves the unknown form to which that pertains. If then, for example,
any one were to ask, What is temetum (for I had instanced this word
already), and it were said to him, What does this matter to you? he
will answer, Lest perhaps I hear some one speaking, and understand him
not; or perhaps read the word somewhere, and know not what the writer
meant. Who, pray, would say to such an inquirer, Do not care about
understanding what you hear; do not care about knowing what you read?
For almost every rational soul quickly discerns the beauty of that
knowledge, through which the thoughts of men are mutually made known
by the enunciation of significant words; and it is on account of this
fitness thus known, and because known therefore loved, that such an
unknown word is studiously sought out. When then he hears and learns
that wine was called "temetum" by our forefathers, but that the word
is already quite obsolete in our present usage of language, he will
think perhaps that he has still need of the word on account of this or
that book of those forefathers. But if he holds these also to be
superfluous, perhaps he does now come to think the word not worth
remembering, since he sees it has nothing to do with that species of
learning which he knows with the mind, and gazes upon, and so loves.
3. Wherefore in all cases the love of a studious mind, that is, of one
that wishes to know what it does not know, is not the love of that
thing which it does not know, but of that which it knows; on account
of which it wishes to know what it does not know. Or if it is so
inquisitive as to be carried away, not for any other cause known to
it, but by the mere love of knowing things unknown; then such an
inquisitive person is, doubtless distinguishable from an ordinary
student, yet does not, any more than he, love things he does not know;
nay, on the contrary, he is more fitly said to hate things he knows
not, of which he wishes that there should be none, in wishing to know
everything. But lest any one should lay before us a more difficult
question, by declaring that it is just as impossible for any one to
hate what he does not know, as to love what he does not know, we will
not withstand what is true; but it must be understood that it is not
the same thing to say he loves to know things unknown, as to say he
loves things unknown. For it is possible that a man may love to know
things unknown; but it is not possible that he should love things
unknown. For the word to know is not placed there without meaning;
since he who loves to know things unknown, does not love the unknown
things themselves, but the knowing of them. And unless he knew what
knowing means, no one could say confidently, either that he knew or
that he did not know. For not only he who says I know, and says so
truly, must needs know what knowing is; but he also who says, I do not
know, and says so confidently and truly, and knows that he says so
truly, certainly knows what knowing is; for he both distinguishes him
who does not know from him who knows, when he looks into himself and
says truly I do not know; and whereas he knows that he says this
truly, whence should he know it, if he did not know what knowing is?
Footnotes
[723] Wine.
Chapter 2.--No One at All Loves Things Unknown.
4. No studious person, then, no inquisitive person, loves things he
does not know, even while he is urgent with the most vehement desire
to know what he does not know. For he either knows already generically
what he loves, and longs to know it also in some individual or
individuals, which perhaps are praised, but not yet known to him; and
he pictures in his mind an imaginary form by which he may be stirred
to love. And whence does he picture this, except from those things
which he has already known? And yet perhaps he will not love it, if he
find that form which was praised to be unlike that other form which
was figured and in thought most fully known to his mind. And if he has
loved it, he will begin to love it from that time when he learned it;
since a little before, that form which was loved was other than that
which the mind that formed it had been wont to exhibit to itself. But
if he shall find it similar to that form which report had proclaimed,
and to be such that he could truly say I was already loving thee; yet
certainly not even then did he love a form he did not know, since he
had known it in that likeness. Or else we see somewhat in the species
of the eternal reason, and therein love it; and when this is
manifested in some image of a temporal thing, and we believe the
praises of those who have made trial of it, and so love it, then we do
not love anything unknown, according to that which we have already
sufficiently discussed above. Or else, again, we love something known,
and on account of it seek something unknown; and so it is by no means
the love of the thing unknown that possesses us, but the love of the
thing known, to which we know the unknown thing belongs, so that we
know that too which we seek still as unknown; as a little before I
said of an unknown word. Or else, again, every one loves the very
knowing itself, as no one can fail to know who desires to know
anything. For these reasons they seem to love things unknown who wish
to know anything which they do not know, and who, on account of their
vehement desire of inquiry, cannot be said to be without love. But how
different the case really is, and that nothing at all can be loved
which is not known, I think I must have persuaded every one who
carefully looks upon truth. But since the examples which we have given
belong to those who desire to know something which they themselves are
not, we must take thought lest perchance some new notion appear, when
the mind desires to know itself.
Chapter 3.--That When the Mind Loves Itself, It is Not Unknown to
Itself.
5. What, then, does the mind love, when it seeks ardently to know
itself, whilst it is still unknown to itself? For, behold, the mind
seeks to know itself, and is excited thereto by studious zeal. It
loves, therefore; but what does it love? Is it itself? But how can
this be when it does not yet know itself, and no one can love what he
does not know? Is it that report has declared to it its own species,
in like way as we commonly hear of people who are absent? Perhaps,
then, it does not love itself, but loves that which it imagines of
itself, which is perhaps widely different from what itself is: or if
the phantasy in the mind is like the mind itself, and so when it loves
this fancied image, it loves itself before it knew itself, because it
gazes upon that which is like itself; then it knew other minds from
which to picture itself, and so is known to itself generically. Why,
then, when it knows other minds, does it not know itself, since
nothing can possibly be more present to it than itself? But if, as
other eyes are more known to the eyes of the body, than those eyes are
to themselves; then let it not seek itself, because it never will find
itself. For eyes can never see themselves except in looking-glasses;
and it cannot be supposed in any way that anything of that kind can be
applied also to the contemplation of incorporeal things, so that the
mind should know itself, as it were, in a looking-glass. Or does it
see in the reason of eternal truth how beautiful it is to know one's
self, and so loves this which it sees, and studies to bring it to pass
in itself? because, although it is not known to itself, yet it is
known to it how good it is, that it should be known to itself. And
this, indeed, is very wonderful, that it does not yet know itself, and
yet knows already how excellent a thing it is to know itself. Or does
it see some most excellent end, viz. its own serenity and blessedness,
by some hidden remembrance, which has not abandoned it, although it
has gone far onwards, and believes that it cannot attain to that same
end unless it know itself? And so while it loves that, it seeks this;
and loves that which is known, on account of which it seeks that which
is unknown. But why should the remembrance of its own blessedness be
able to last, and the remembrance of itself not be able to last as
well; that so it should know itself which wishes to attain, as well as
know that to which it wishes to attain? Or when it loves to know
itself, does it love, not itself, which it does not yet know, but the
very act of knowing; and feel the more annoyed that itself is wanting
to its own knowledge wherewith it wishes to embrace all things? And it
knows what it is to know; and whilst it loves this, which it knows,
desires also to know itself. Whereby, then, does it know its own
knowing, if it does not know itself? For it knows that it knows other
things, but that it does not know itself; for it is from hence that it
knows also what knowing is. In what way, then, does that which does
not know itself, know itself as knowing anything? For it does not know
that some other mind knows, but that itself does so. Therefore it
knows itself. Further, when it seeks to know itself, it knows itself
now as seeking. Therefore again it knows itself. And hence it cannot
altogether not know itself, when certainly it does so far know itself
as that it knows itself as not knowing itself. But if it does not know
itself not to know itself, then it does not seek to know itself. And
therefore, in the very fact that it seeks itself, it is clearly
convicted of being more known to itself than unknown. For it knows
itself as seeking and as not knowing itself, in that it seeks to know
itself.
Chapter 4.--How the Mind Knows Itself, Not in Part, But as a Whole.
6. What then shall we say? Does that which knows itself in part, not
know itself in part? But it is absurd to say, that it does not as a
whole know what it knows. I do not say, it knows wholly; but what it
knows, it as a whole knows. When therefore it knows anything about
itself, which it can only know as a whole, it knows itself as a whole.
But it does know that itself knows something, while yet except as a
whole it cannot know anything. Therefore it knows itself as a whole.
Further, what in it is so known to itself, as that it lives? And it
cannot at once be a mind, and not live, while it has also something
over and above, viz., that it understands: for the souls of beasts
also live, but do not understand. As therefore a mind is a whole mind,
so it lives as a whole. But it knows that it lives. Therefore it knows
itself as a whole. Lastly, when the mind seeks to know itself, it
already knows that it is a mind: otherwise it knows not whether it
seeks itself, and perhaps seeks one thing while intending to seek
another. For it might happen that itself was not a mind, and so, in
seeking to know a mind, that it did not seek to know itself. Wherefore
since the mind, when it seeks to know what mind is, knows that it
seeks itself, certainly it knows that itself is a mind. Furthermore,
if it knows this in itself, that it is a mind, and a whole mind, then
it knows itself as a whole. But suppose it did not know itself to be a
mind, but in seeking itself only knew that it did seek itself. For so,
too, it may possibly seek one thing for another, if it does not know
this: but that it may not seek one thing for another, without doubt it
knows what it seeks. But if it knows what it seeks, and seeks itself,
then certainly it knows itself. What therefore more does it seek? But
if it knows itself in part, but still seeks itself in part, then it
seeks not itself, but part of itself. For when we speak of the mind
itself, we speak of it as a whole. Further, because it knows that it
is not yet found by itself as a whole, it knows how much the whole is.
And so it seeks that which is wanting, as we are wont to seek to
recall to the mind something that has slipped from the mind, but has
not altogether gone away from it; since we can recognize it, when it
has come back, to be the same thing that we were seeking. But how can
mind come into mind, as though it were possible for the mind not to be
in the mind? Add to this, that if, having found a part, it does not
seek itself as a whole, yet it as a whole seeks itself. Therefore as a
whole it is present to itself, and there is nothing left to be sought:
for that is wanting which is sought, not the mind which seeks. Since
therefore it as a whole seeks itself, nothing of it is wanting. Or if
it does not as a whole seek itself, but the part which has been found
seeks the part which has not yet been found then the mind does not
seek itself, of which no part seeks itself. For the part which has
been found, does not seek itself; nor yet does the part itself which
has not yet been found, seek itself; since it is sought by that part
which has been already found. Wherefore, since neither the mind as a
whole seeks itself, nor does any part of it seek itself, the mind does
not seek itself at all.
Chapter 5.--Why the Soul is Enjoined to Know Itself. Whence Come the
Errors of the Mind Concerning Its Own Substance.
7. Why therefore is it enjoined upon it, that it should know itself? I
suppose, in order that, it may consider itself, and live according to
its own nature; that is, seek to be regulated according to its own
nature, viz., under Him to whom it ought to be subject, and above
those things to which it is to be preferred; under Him by whom it
ought to be ruled, above those things which it ought to rule. For it
does many things through vicious desire, as though in forgetfulness of
itself. For it sees some things intrinsically excellent, in that more
excellent nature which is God: and whereas it ought to remain
steadfast that it may enjoy them, it is turned away from Him, by
wishing to appropriate those things to itself, and not to be like to
Him by His gift, but to be what He is by its own, and it begins to
move and slip gradually down into less and less, which it thinks to be
more and more; for it is neither sufficient for itself, nor is
anything at all sufficient for it, if it withdraw from Him who is
alone sufficient: and so through want and distress it becomes too
intent upon its own actions and upon the unquiet delights which it
obtains through them: and thus, by the desire of acquiring knowledge
from those things that are without, the nature of which it knows and
loves, and which it feels can be lost unless held fast with anxious
care, it loses its security, and thinks of itself so much the less, in
proportion as it feels the more secure that it cannot lose itself. So,
whereas it is one thing not to know oneself, and another not to think
of oneself (for we do not say of the man that is skilled in much
learning, that he is ignorant of grammar, when he is only not thinking
of it, because he is thinking at the time of the art of
medicine);--whereas, then, I say it is one thing not to know oneself,
and another not to think of oneself, such is the strength of love,
that the mind draws in with itself those things which it has long
thought of with love, and has grown into them by the close adherence
of diligent study, even when it returns in some way to think of
itself. And because these things are corporeal which it loved
externally through the carnal senses; and because it has become
entangled with them by a kind of daily familiarity, and yet cannot
carry those corporeal things themselves with itself internally as it
were into the region of incorporeal nature; therefore it combines
certain images of them, and thrusts them thus made from itself into
itself. For it gives to the forming of them somewhat of its own
substance, yet preserves the while something by which it may judge
freely of the species of those images; and this something is more
properly the mind, that is, the rational understanding, which is
preserved that it may judge. For we see that we have those parts of
the soul which are informed by the likenesses of corporeal things, in
common also with beasts.
Chapter 6.--The Opinion Which the Mind Has of Itself is Deceitful.
8. But the mind errs, when it so lovingly and intimately connects
itself with these images, as even to consider itself to be something
of the same kind. For so it is conformed to them to some extent, not
by being this, but by thinking it is so: not that it thinks itself to
be an image, but outright that very thing itself of which it
entertains the image. For there still lives in it the power of
distinguishing the corporeal thing which it leaves without, from the
image of that corporeal thing which it contains therefrom within
itself: except when these images are so projected as if felt without
and not thought within, as in the case of people who are asleep, or
mad, or in a trance.
Chapter 7.--The Opinions of Philosophers Respecting the Substance of
the Soul. The Error of Those Who are of Opinion that the Soul is
Corporeal, Does Not Arise from Defective Knowledge of the Soul, But
from Their Adding There to Something Foreign to It. What is Meant by
Finding.
9. When, therefore, it thinks itself to be something of this kind, it
thinks itself to be a corporeal thing; and since it is perfectly
conscious of its own superiority, by which it rules the body, it has
hence come to pass that the question has been raised what part of the
body has the greater power in the body; and the opinion has been held
that this is the mind, nay, that it is even the whole soul altogether.
And some accordingly think it to be the blood, others the brain,
others the heart; not as the Scripture says, "I will praise Thee, O
Lord, with my whole heart;" and, "Thou shall love the Lord thy God
with all thine heart;" [724] for this word by misapplication or
metaphor is transferred from the body to the soul; but they have
simply thought it to be that small part itself of the body, which we
see when the inward parts are rent asunder. Others, again, have
believed the soul to be made up of very minute and individual
corpustules, which they call atoms, meeting in themselves and
cohering. Others have said that its substance is air, others fire.
Others have been of opinion that it is no substance at all, since they
could not think any substance unless it is body, and they did not find
that the soul was body; but it was in their opinion the tempering
together itself of our body, or the combining together of the
elements, by which that flesh is as it were conjoined. And hence all
of these have held the soul to be mortal; since, whether it were body,
or some combination of body, certainly it could not in either case
continue always without death. But they who have held its substance to
be some kind of life the reverse of corporeal, since they have found
it to be a life that animates and quickens every living body, have by
consequence striven also, according as each was able, to prove it
immortal, since life cannot be without life.
For as to that fifth kind of body, I know not what, which some have
added to the four well-known elements of the world, and have said that
the soul was made of this, I do not think we need spend time in
discussing it in this place. For either they mean by body what we mean
by it, viz., that of which a part is less than the whole in extension
of place, and they are to be reckoned among those who have believed
the mind to be corporeal: or if they call either all substance, or all
changeable substance, body, whereas they know that not all substance
is contained in extension of place by any length and breadth and
height, we need not contend with them about a question of words.
10. Now, in the case of all these opinions, any one who sees that the
nature of the mind is at once substance, and yet not corporeal,--that
is, that it does not occupy a less extension of place with a less part
of itself, and a greater with a greater,--must needs see at the same
time that they who are of opinion that it is corporeal [725] do not
err from defect of knowledge concerning mind, but because they
associate with it qualities without which they are not able to
conceive any nature at all. For if you bid them conceive of existence
that is without corporeal phantasms, they hold it merely nothing. And
so the mind would not seek itself, as though wanting to itself. For
what is so present to knowledge as that which is present to the mind?
Or what is so present to the mind as the mind itself? And hence what
is called "invention," if we consider the origin of the word, what
else does it mean, unless that to find out [726] is to "come into"
that which is sought? Those things accordingly which come into the
mind as it were of themselves, are not usually said to be found out,
[727] although they may be said to be known; since we did not endeavor
by seeking to come into them, that is to invent or find them out. And
therefore, as the mind itself really seeks those things which are
sought by the eyes or by any other sense of the body (for the mind
directs even the carnal sense, and then finds out or invents, when
that sense comes to the things which are sought); so, too, it finds
out or invents other things which it ought to know, not with the
medium of corporeal sense, but through itself, when it "comes into"
them; and this, whether in the case of the higher substance that is in
God, or of the other parts of the soul; just as it does when it judges
of bodily images themselves, for it finds these within, in the soul,
impressed through the body.
Footnotes
[724] Ps. ix., cxi., and cxxxviii., Deut. vi. 5, and Matt. xxii. 37
[725] [The distinction between corporeal and incorporeal substance is
one that Augustin often insists upon. See Confessions VII. i-iii. The
doctrine that all substance is extended body, and that there is no
such entity as spiritual unextended substance, is combatted by Plato
in the Theatetus. For a history of the contest and an able defence of
the substantiality of spirit, see Cudworth's Intellectual System, III.
384 sq. Harrison's Ed.--W.G.T.S.]
[726] Invenire
[727] Inventa
Chapter 8.--How the Soul Inquires into Itself. Whence Comes the Error
of the Soul Concerning Itself.
11. It is then a wonderful question, in what manner the soul seeks and
finds itself; at what it aims in order to seek, or whither it comes,
that it may come into or find out. For what is so much in the mind as
the mind itself? But because it is in those things which it thinks of
with love, and is wont to be in sensible, that is, in corporeal things
with love, it is unable to be in itself without the images of those
corporeal things. And hence shameful error arises to block its way,
whilst it cannot separate from itself the images of sensible things,
so as to see itself alone. For they have marvellously cohered with it
by the close adhesion of love. And herein consists its uncleanness;
since, while it strives to think of itself alone, it fancies itself to
be that, without which it cannot think of itself. When, therefore, it
is bidden to become acquainted with itself, let it not seek itself as
though it were withdrawn from itself; but let it withdraw that which
it has added to itself. For itself lies more deeply within, not only
than those sensible things, which are clearly without, but also than
the images of them; which are indeed in some part of the soul, viz.,
that which beasts also have, although these want understanding, which
is proper to the mind. As therefore the mind is within, it goes forth
in some sort from itself, when it exerts the affection of love towards
these, as it were, footprints of many acts of attention. And these
footprints are, as it were, imprinted on the memory, at the time when
the corporeal things which are without are perceived in such way, that
even when those corporeal things are absent, yet the images of them
are at hand to those who think of them. Therefore let the mind become
acquainted with itself, and not seek itself as if it were absent; but
fix upon itself the act of [voluntary] attention, by which it was
wandering among other things, and let it think of itself. So it will
see that at no time did it ever not love itself, at no time did it
ever not know itself; but by loving another thing together with itself
it has confounded itself with it, and in some sense has grown one with
it. And so, while it embraces diverse things, as though they were one,
it has come to think those things to be one which are diverse.
Chapter 9.--The Mind Knows Itself, by the Very Act of Understanding
the Precept to Know Itself.
12. Let it not therefore seek to discern itself as though absent, but
take pains to discern itself as present. Nor let it take knowledge of
itself as if it did not know itself, but let it distinguish itself
from that which it knows to be another. For how will it take pains to
obey that very precept which is given it, "Know thyself," if it knows
not either what "know" means or what "thyself" means? But if it knows
both, then it knows also itself. Since "know thyself" is not so said
to the mind as is "Know the cherubim and the seraphim;" for they are
absent, and we believe concerning them, and according to that belief
they are declared to be certain celestial powers. Nor yet again as it
is said, Know the will of that man: for this it is not within our
reach to perceive at all, either by sense or understanding, unless by
corporeal signs actually set forth; and this in such a way that we
rather believe than understand. Nor again as it is said to a man,
Behold thy own face; which he can only do in a looking-glass. For even
our own face itself is out of the reach of our own seeing it; because
it is not there where our look can be directed. But when it is said to
the mind, Know thyself; then it knows itself by that very act by which
it understands the word "thyself;" and this for no other reason than
that it is present to itself. But if it does not understand what is
said, then certainly it does not do as it is bid to do. And therefore
it is bidden to do that thing which it does do, when it understands
the very precept that bids it.
Chapter 10.--Every Mind Knows Certainly Three Things Concerning
Itself--That It Understands, that It Is, and that It Lives.
13. Let it not then add anything to that which it knows itself to be,
when it is bidden to know itself. For it knows, at any rate, that this
is said to itself; namely, to the self that is, and that lives, and
that understands. But a dead body also is, and cattle live; but
neither a dead body nor cattle understand. Therefore it so knows that
it so is, and that it so lives, as an understanding is and lives.
When, therefore, for example's sake, the mind thinks itself air, it
thinks that air understands; it knows, however, that itself
understands, but it does not know itself to be air, but only thinks
so. Let it separate that which it thinks itself; let it discern that
which it knows; let this remain to it, about which not even have they
doubted who have thought the mind to be this corporeal thing or that.
For certainly every mind does not consider itself to be air; but some
think themselves fire, others the brain, and some one kind of
corporeal thing, others another, as I have mentioned before; yet all
know that they themselves understand, and are, and live; but they
refer understanding to that which they understand, but to be, and to
live, to themselves. And no one doubts, either that no one understands
who does not live, or that no one lives of whom it is not true that he
is; and that therefore by consequence that which understands both is
and lives; not as a dead body is which does not live, nor as a soul
lives which does not understand, but in some proper and more excellent
manner. Further, they know that they will, and they equally know that
no one can will who is not and who does not live; and they also refer
that will itself to something which they will with that will. They
know also that they remember; and they know at the same time that
nobody could remember, unless he both was and lived; but we refer
memory itself also to something, in that we remember those things.
Therefore the knowledge and science of many things are contained in
two of these three, memory and understanding; but will must be
present, that we may enjoy or use them. For we enjoy things known, in
which things themselves the will finds delight for their own sake, and
so reposes; but we use those things, which we refer to some other
thing which we are to enjoy. Neither is the life of man vicious and
culpable in any other way, than as wrongly using and wrongly enjoying.
But it is no place here to discuss this.
14. But since we treat of the nature of the mind, let us remove from
our consideration all knowledge which is received from without,
through the senses of the body; and attend more carefully to the
position which we have laid down, that all minds know and are certain
concerning themselves. For men certainly have doubted whether the
power of living, of remembering, of understanding, of willing, of
thinking, of knowing, of judging, be of air, or of fire, or of the
brain, or of the blood, or of atoms, or besides the usual four
elements of a fifth kind of body, I know not what; or ,whether the
combining or tempering together of this our flesh itself has power to
accomplish these things. And one has attempted to establish this, and
another to establish that. Yet who ever doubts that he himself lives,
and remembers, and understands, and wills, and thinks, and knows, and
judges? Seeing that even if he doubts, he lives; if he doubts, he
remembers why he doubts; if he doubts, he understands that he doubts;
if he doubts, he wishes to be certain; if he doubts, he thinks; if he
doubts, he knows that he does not know; if he doubts, he judges that
he ought not to assent rashly. Whosoever therefore doubts about
anything else, ought not to doubt of all these things; which if they
were not, he would not be able to doubt of anything.
15. They who think the mind to be either a body or the combination or
tempering of the body, will have all these things to seem to be in a
subject, so that the substance is air, or fire, or some other
corporeal thing, which they think to be the mind; but that the
understanding (intelligentia) is in this corporeal thing as its
quality, so that this corporeal thing is the subject, but the
understanding is in the subject: viz. that the mind is the subject,
which they judge to be a corporeal thing, but the understanding
[intelligence], or any other of those things which we have mentioned
as certain to us, is in that subject. They also hold nearly the same
opinion who deny the mind itself to be body, but think it to be the
combination or tempering together of the body; for there is this
difference, that the former say that the mind itself is the substance,
in which the understanding [intelligence] is, as in a subject; but the
latter say that the mind itself is in a subject, viz. in the body, of
which it is the combination or tempering together. And hence, by
consequence, what else can they think, except that the understanding
also is in the same body as in a subject?
16. And all these do not perceive that the mind knows itself, even
when it seeks for itself, as we have already shown. But nothing is at
all rightly said to be known while its substance is not known. And
therefore, when the mind knows itself, it knows its own substance; and
when it is certain about itself, it as certain about its own
substance. But it is certain about itself, as those things which are
said above prove convincingly; although it is not at all certain
whether itself is air, or fire, or some body, or some function of
body. Therefore it is not any of these. And to that whole which is
bidden to know itself, belongs this, that it is certain that it is not
any of those things of which it is uncertain, and is certain that it
is that only, which only it is certain that it is. For it thinks in
this way of fire, or air, and whatever else of the body it thinks of.
Neither can it in any way be brought to pass that it should so think
that which itself is, as it thinks that which itself is not. Since it
thinks all these things through an imaginary phantasy, whether fire,
or air, or this or that body, or that part or combination and
tempering together of the body: nor assuredly is it said to be all
those things, but some one of them. But if it were any one of them, it
would think this one in a different manner from the rest viz. not
through an imaginary phantasy, as absent things are thought, which
either themselves or some of like kind have been touched by the bodily
sense; but by some inward, not feigned, but true presence (for nothing
is more present to it than itself); just as it thinks that itself
lives, and remembers, and understands, and wills. For it knows these
things in itself, and does not imagine them as though it had touched
them by the sense outside itself, as corporeal things are touched. And
if it attaches nothing to itself from the thought of these things, so
as to think itself to be something of the kind, then whatsoever
remains to it from itself that alone is itself.
Chapter 11.--In Memory, Understanding [or Intelligence], and Will, We
Have to Note Ability, Learning, and Use. Memory, Understanding, and
Will are One Essentially, and Three Relatively.
17. Putting aside, then, for a little while all other things, of which
the mind is certain concerning itself, let us especially consider and
discuss these three--memory, understanding, will. For we may commonly
discern in these three the character of the abilities of the young
also; since the more tenaciously and easily a boy remembers, and the
more acutely he understands, and the more ardently he studies, the
more praiseworthy is he in point of ability. But when the question is
about any one's learning, then we ask not how solidly and easily he
remembers, or how shrewdly he understands; but what it is that he
remembers, and what it is that he understands. And because the mind is
regarded as praiseworthy, not only as being learned, but also as being
good, one gives heed not only to what he remembers and what he
understands, but also to what he wills (velit); not how ardently he
wills, but first what it is he wills, and then how greatly he wills
it. For the mind that loves eagerly is then to be praised, when it
loves that which ought to be loved eagerly. Since, then, we speak of
these three--ability, knowledge, use--the first of these is to be
considered under the three heads, of what a man can do in memory, and
understanding, and will. The second of them is to be considered in
regard to that which any one has in his memory and in his
understanding, which he has attained by a studious will. But the
third, viz. use, lies in the will, which handles those things that are
contained in the memory and understanding, whether it refer them to
anything further, or rest satisfied with them as an end. For to use,
is to take up something into the power of the will; and to enjoy, is
to use with joy, not any longer of hope, but of the actual thing.
Accordingly, every one who enjoys, uses; for he takes up something
into the power of the will, wherein he also is satisfied as with an
end. But not every one who uses, enjoys, if he has sought after that,
which he takes up into the power of the will, not on account of the
thing itself, but on account of something else.
18. Since, then, these three, memory, understanding, will, are not
three lives, but one life; nor three minds, but one mind; it follows
certainly that neither are they three substances, but one substance.
Since memory, which is called life, and mind, and substance, is so
called in respect to itself; but it is called memory, relatively to
something. And I should say the same also of understanding and of
will, since they are called understanding and will relatively to
something; but each in respect to itself is life, and mind, and
essence. And hence these three are one, in that they are one life, one
mind, one essence; and whatever else they are severally called in
respect to themselves, they are called also together, not plurally,
but in the singular number. But they are three, in that wherein they
are mutually referred to each other; and if they were not equal, and
this not only each to each, but also each to all, they certainly could
not mutually contain each other; for not only is each contained by
each, but also all by each. For I remember that I have memory and
understanding, and will; and I understand that I understand, and will,
and remember; and I will that I will, and remember, and understand;
and I remember together my whole memory, and understanding, and will.
For that of my memory which I do not remember, is not in my memory;
and nothing is so much in the memory as memory itself. Therefore I
remember the whole memory. Also, whatever I understand I know that I
understand, and I know that I will whatever I will; but whatever I
know I remember. Therefore I remember the whole of my understanding,
and the whole of my will. Likewise, when I understand these three
things, I understand them together as whole. For there is none of
things intelligible which I do not understand, except what I do not
know; but what I do not know, I neither remember, nor will. Therefore,
whatever of things intelligible I do not understand, it follows also
that I neither remember nor will. And whatever of things intelligible
I remember and will, it follows that I understand. My will also
embraces my whole understanding and my whole memory whilst I use the
whole that I understand and remember. And, therefore, while all are
mutually comprehended by each, and as wholes, each as a whole is equal
to each as a whole, and each as a whole at the same time to all as
wholes; and these three are one, one life, one mind, one essence.
[728]
Footnotes
[728] [This ternary of memory, understanding, and will, is a better
analogue to the Trinity than the preceding one in chapter IX--namely,
mind, knowledge, and love. Memory, understanding, and will have equal
substantiality, while mind, knowledge, and love have not. The former
are three faculties, in each of which is the whole mind or spirit. The
memory is the whole mind as remembering; the understanding is the
whole mind as cognizing; and the will is the whole mind as
determining. The one essence of the mind is in each of these three
modes, each of which is distinct from the others; and yet there are
not three essences or minds. In the other ternary, of mind, knowledge,
and love, the last two are not faculties but single acts of the mind.
A particular act of cognition is not the whole mind in the general
mode of cognition. This would make it a faculty. A particular act of
loving, or of willing, is not the whole mind in the general mode of
loving, or of willing. This would make the momentary and transient act
a permanent faculty. This ternary fails, as we have noticed in a
previous annotation (IX. ii. 2), in that only the mind is a substance.
The ternary of memory, understanding, and will is an adequate analogue
to the Trinity in respect to equal substantiality. But it fails when
the separate consciousness of the Trinitarian distinctions is brought
into consideration. The three faculties of memory, understanding, and
will, are not so objective to each other as to admit of three forms of
consciousness, of the use of the personal pronouns, and of the
personal actions that are ascribed to the Father, Son, and Holy
Spirit. It also fails, in that these three are not all the modes of
the mind. There are other faculties: e. g., the imagination. The whole
essence of the mind is in this also.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 12.--The Mind is an Image of the Trinity in Its Own Memory,
and Understanding, and Will.
19. Are we, then, now to go upward, with whatever strength of purpose
we may, to that chiefest and highest essence, of which the human mind
is an inadequate image, yet an image? Or are these same three things
to be yet more distinctly made plain in the soul, by means of those
things which we receive from without, through the bodily sense,
wherein the knowledge of corporeal things is impressed upon us in
time? Since we found the mind itself to be such in its own memory, and
understanding, and will, that since it was understood always to know
and always to will itself, it was understood also at the same time
always to remember itself, always to understand and love itself,
although not always to think of itself as separate from those things
which are not itself; and hence its memory of itself, and
understanding of itself, are with difficult discerned in it. For in
this case, where these two things are very closely conjoined, and one
is not preceded by the other by any time at all, it looks as if they
were not two things, but one called by two names; and love itself is
not so plainly felt to exist when the sense of need does not disclose
it, since what is loved is always at hand. And hence these things may
be more lucidly set forth, even to men of duller minds, if such topics
are treated of as are brought within reach of the mind in time, and
happen to it in time; while it remembers what it did not remember
before, and sees what it did not see before, and loves what it did not
love before. But this discussion demands now another beginning, by
reason of the measure of the present book.
.
Book XI.
A kind of image of the Trinity is pointed out, even in the outer man;
first of all, in those things which are perceived from without, viz.
in the bodily object that is seen, and in the form that is impressed
by it upon the sight of the seer, and in the purpose of the will that
combines the two; although these three are neither mutually equal, nor
of one substance. Next, a kind of trinity, in three somewhats of one
substance, is observed to exist in the mind itself, as it were
introduced there from those things that are perceived from without;
viz. the image of the bodily object which is in the memory, and the
impression formed therefrom when the mind's eye of the thinker is
turned to it, and the purpose of the will combining both. And this
latter trinity is also said to pertain to the outer man, in that it is
introduced into the mind from bodily objects, which are perceived from
without.
Chapter 1.--A Trace of the Trinity Also In the Outer Man.
1. No one doubts that, as the inner man is endued with understanding,
so is the outer with bodily sense. Let us try, then, if we can, to
discover in this outer man also, some trace, however slight, of the
Trinity, not that itself also is in the same manner the image of God.
For the opinion of the apostle is evident, which declares the inner
man to be renewed in the knowledge of God after the image of Him that
created him: [729] whereas he says also in another place, "But though
our outer man perish, yet the inward man is renewed day by day." [730]
Let us seek, then, so far as we can, in that which perishes, some
image of the Trinity, if not so express, yet perhaps more easy to be
discerned. For that outer man also is not called man to no purpose,
but because there is in it some likeness of the inner man. And owing
to that very order of our condition whereby we are made mortal and
fleshly, we handle things visible more easily and more familiarly than
things intelligible; since the former are outward, the latter inward;
and the former are perceived by the bodily sense, the latter are
understood by the mind; and we ourselves, i.e. our minds, are not
sensible things, that is, bodies, but intelligible things, since we
are life. And yet, as I said, we are so familiarly occupied with
bodies, and our thought has projected itself outwardly with so
wonderful a proclivity towards bodies, that, when it has been
withdrawn from the uncertainty of things corporeal, that it may be
fixed with a much more certain and stable knowledge in that which is
spirit, it flies back to those bodies, and seeks rest there whence it
has drawn weakness. And to this its feebleness we must suit our
argument; so that, if we would endeavor at any time to distinguish
more aptly, and intimate more readily, the inward spiritual thing, we
must take examples of likenesses from outward things pertaining to the
body. The outer man, then, endued as he is with the bodily sense, is
conversant with bodies. And this bodily sense, as is easily observed,
is fivefold; seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting, touching. But it is
both a good deal of trouble, and is not necessary, that we should
inquire of all these five senses about that which we seek. For that
which one of them declares to us, holds also good in the rest. Let us
use, then, principally the testimony of the eyes. For this bodily
sense far surpasses the rest; and in proportion to its difference of
kind, is nearer to the sight of the mind.
Footnotes
[729] Col. iii. 10
[730] 2 Cor. iv. 16
Chapter 2.--A Certain Trinity in the Sight. That There are Three
Things in Sight, Which Differ in Their Own Nature. In What Manner from
a Visible Thing Vision is Produced, or the Image of that Thing Which
is Seen. The Matter is Shown More Clearly by an Example. How These
Three Combine in One.
2. When, then, we see any corporeal object, these three things, as is
most easy to do, are to be considered and distinguished: First, the
object itself which we see; whether a stone, or flame, or any other
thing that can be seen by the eyes; and this certainly might exist
also already before it was seen; next, vision or the act of seeing,
which did not exist before we perceived the object itself which is
presented to the sense; in the third place, that which keeps the sense
of the eye in the object seen, so long as it is seen, viz. the
attention of the mind. In these three, then, not only is there an
evident distinction, but also a diverse nature. For, first, that
visible body is of a far different nature from the sense of the eyes,
through the incidence of which sense upon it vision arises. And what
plainly is vision itself other than perception informed by that thing
which is perceived? Although there is no vision if the visible object
be withdrawn, nor could there be any vision of the kind at all if
there were no body that could be seen; yet the body by which the sense
of the eyes is informed, when that body is seen, and the form itself
which is imprinted by it upon the sense, which is called vision, are
by no means of the same substance. For the body that is seen is, in
its own nature, separable; but the sense, which was already in the
living subject, even before it saw what it was able to see, when it
fell in with something visible,--or the vision which comes to be in
the sense from the visible body when now brought into connection with
it and seen,--the sense, then, I say, or the vision, that is, the
sense informed from without, belongs to the nature of the living
subject, which is altogether other than that body which we perceive by
seeing, and by which the sense is not so formed as to be sense, but as
to be vision. For unless the sense were also in us before the
presentation to us of the sensible object, we should not differ from
the blind, at times when we are seeing nothing, whether in darkness,
or when our eyes are closed. But we differ from them in this, that
there is in us, even when we are not seeing, that whereby we are able
to see, which is called the sense; whereas this is not in them, nor
are they called blind for any other reason than because they have it
not. Further also, that attention of the mind which keeps the sense in
that thing which we see, and connects both, not only differs from that
visible thing in its nature; in that the one is mind, and the other
body; but also from the sense and the vision itself: since this
attention is the act of the mind alone; but the sense of the eyes is
called a bodily sense, for no other reason than because the eyes
themselves also are members of the body; and although an inanimate
body does not perceive, yet the soul commingled with the body
perceives through a corporeal instrument, and that instrument is
called sense. And this sense, too, is cut off and extinguished by
suffering on the part of the body, when any one is blinded; while the
mind remains the same; and its attention, since the eyes are lost, has
not, indeed, the sense of the body which it may join, by seeing, to
the body without it, and so fix its look thereupon and see it, yet by
the very effort shows that, although the bodily sense be taken away,
itself can neither perish nor be diminished. For there remains
unimpaired a desire [appetitus] of seeing, whether it can be carried
into effect or not. These three, then, the body that is seen, and
vision itself, and the attention of mind which joins both together,
are manifestly distinguishable, not only on account of the properties
of each, but also on account of the difference of their natures.
3. And since, in this case, the sensation does not proceed from that
body which is seen, but from the body of the living being that
perceives, with which the soul is tempered together in some wonderful
way of its own; yet vision is produced, that is, the sense itself is
informed, by the body which is seen; so that now, not only is there
the power of sense, which can exist also unimpaired even in darkness,
provided the eyes are sound, but also a sense actually informed, which
is called vision. Vision, then, is produced from a thing that is
visible; but not from that alone, unless there be present also one who
sees. Therefore vision is produced from a thing that is visible,
together with one who sees; in such way that, on the part of him who
sees, there is the sense of seeing and the intention of looking and
gazing at the object; while yet that information of the sense, which
is called vision, is imprinted only by the body which is seen, that
is, by some visible thing; which being taken away, that form remains
no more which was in the sense so long as that which was seen was
present: yet the sense itself remains, which existed also before
anything was perceived; just as the trace of a thing in water remains
so long as the body itself, which is impressed on it, is in the water;
but if this has been taken away, there will no longer be any such
trace, although the water remains, which existed also before it took
the form of that body. And therefore we cannot, indeed, say that a
visible thing produces the sense; yet it produces the form, which is,
as it were, its own likeness, which comes to be in the sense, when we
perceive anything by seeing. But we do not distinguish, through the
same sense, the form of the body which we see, from the form which is
produced by it in the sense of him who sees; since the union of the
two is so close that there is no room for distinguishing them. But we
rationally infer that we could not have sensation at all, unless some
similitude of the body seen was wrought in our own sense. For when a
ring is imprinted on wax, it does not follow that no image is
produced, because we cannot discern it unless when it has been
separated. But since, after the wax is separated, what was made
remains, so that it can be seen; we are on that account easily
persuaded that there was already also in the wax a form impressed from
the ring before it was separated from it. But if the ring were
imprinted upon a fluid, no image at all would appear when it was
withdrawn; and yet none the less for this ought the reason to discern
that there was in that fluid before the ring was withdrawn a form of
the ring produced from the ring, which is to be distinguished from
that form which is in the ring, whence that form was produced which
ceases to be when the ring is withdrawn, although that in the ring
remains, whence the other was produced. And so the [sensuous]
perception of the eyes may not be supposed to contain no image of the
body, which is seen as long as it is seen, [merely] because when that
is withdrawn the image does not remain. And hence it is very difficult
to persuade men of duller mind that an image of the visible thing is
formed in our sense, when we see it, and that this same form is
vision.
4. But if any perhaps attend to what I am about to mention, they will
find no such trouble in this inquiry. Commonly, when we have looked
for some little time at a light, and then shut our eyes, there seem to
play before our eyes certain bright colors variously changing
themselves, and shining less and less until they wholly cease; and
these we must understand to be the remains of that form which was
wrought in the sense, while the shining body was seen, and that these
variations take place in them as they slowly and step by step fade
away. For the lattices, too, of windows, should we happen to be gazing
at them, appear often in these colors; so that it is evident that our
sense is affected by such impressions from that thing which is seen.
That form therefore existed also while we were seeing, and at that
time it was more clear and express. But it was then closely joined
with the species of that thing which was being perceived, so that it
could not be at all distinguished from it; and this was vision itself.
Why, even when the little flame of a lamp is in some way, as it were,
doubled by the divergent rays of the eyes, a twofold vision comes to
pass, although the thing which is seen is one. For the same rays, as
they shoot forth each from its own eye, are affected severally, in
that they are not allowed to meet evenly and conjointly, in regarding
that corporeal thing, so that one combined view might be formed from
both. And so, if we shut one eye, we shall not see two flames, but one
as it really is. But why, if we shut the left eye, that appearance
ceases to be seen, which was on the right; and if, in turn, we shut
the right eye, that drops out of existence which was on the left, is a
matter both tedious in itself, and not necessary at all to our present
subject to inquire and discuss. For it is enough for the business in
hand to consider, that unless some image, precisely like the thing we
perceive, were produced in our sense, the appearance of the flame
would not be doubled according to the number of the eyes; since a
certain way of perceiving has been employed, which could separate the
union of rays. Certainly nothing that is really single can be seen as
if it were double by one eye, draw it down, or press, or distort it as
you please, if the other is shut.
5. The case then being so, let us remember how these three things,
although diverse in nature, are tempered together into a kind of
unity; that is, the form of the body which is seen, and the image of
it impressed on the sense, which is vision or sense informed, and the
will of the mind which applies the sense to the sensible thing, and
retains the vision itself in it. The first of these, that is, the
visible thing itself, does not belong to the nature of the living
being, except when we discern our own body. But the second belongs to
that nature to this extent, that it is wrought in the body, and
through the body in the soul; for it is wrought in the sense, which is
neither without the body nor without the soul. But the third is of the
soul alone, because it is the will. Although then the substances of
these three are so different, yet they coalesce into such a unity that
the two former can scarcely be distinguished, even with the
intervention of the reason as judge, namely the form of the body which
is seen, and the image of it which is wrought in the sense, that is,
vision. And the will so powerfully combines these two, as both to
apply the sense, in order to be informed, to that thing which is
perceived, and to retain it when informed in that thing. And if it is
so vehement that it can be called love, or desire, or lust, it
vehemently affects also the rest of the body of the living being; and
where a duller and harder matter does not resist, changes it into like
shape and color. One may see the little body of a chameleon vary with
ready change, according to the colors which it sees. And in the case
of other animals, since their grossness of flesh does not easily admit
change, the offspring, for the most part, betray the particular
fancies of the mothers, whatever it is that they have beheld with
special delight. For the more tender, and so to say, the more
formable, are the primary seeds, the more effectually and capably they
follow the bent of the soul of the mother, and the phantasy that is
wrought in it through that body, which it has greedily beheld.
Abundant instances might be adduced, but one is sufficient, taken from
the most trustworthy books; viz. what Jacob did, that the sheep and
goats might give birth to offspring of various colors, by placing
variegated rods before them in the troughs of water for them to look
at as they drank, at the time they had conceived. [731]
Footnotes
[731] Gen. xxx. 37-41
Chapter 3.--The Unity of the Three Takes Place in Thought, Viz Of
Memory, of Ternal Vision,and of Will Combining Both.
6. The rational soul, however, lives in a degenerate fashion, when it
lives according to a trinity of the outer man; that is, when it
applies to those things which form the bodily sense from without, not
a praiseworthy will, by which to refer them to some useful end, but a
base desire, by which to cleave to them. Since even if the form of the
body, which was corporeally perceived, be withdrawn, its likeness
remains in the memory, to which the will may again direct its eye, so
as to be formed thence from within, as the sense was formed from
without by the presentation of the sensible body. And so that trinity
is produced from memory, from internal vision, and from the will which
unites both. And when these three things are combined into one, from
that combination [732] itself they are called conception. [733] And in
these three there is no longer any diversity of substance. For neither
is the sensible body there, which is altogether distinct from the
nature of the living being, nor is the bodily sense there informed so
as to produce vision, nor does the will itself perform its office of
applying the sense, that is to be informed, to the sensible body, and
of retaining it in it when informed; but in place of that bodily
species which was perceived from without, there comes the memory
retaining that species which the soul has imbibed through the bodily
sense; and in place of that vision which was outward when the sense
was informed through the sensible body, there comes a similar vision
within, while the eye of the mind is informed from that which the
memory retains, and the corporeal things that are thought of are
absent; and the will itself, as before it applied the sense yet to be
informed to the corporeal thing presented from without, and united it
thereto when informed, so now converts the vision of the recollecting
mind to memory, in order that the mental sight may be informed by that
which the memory has retained, and so there may be in the conception a
like vision. And as it was the reason that distinguished the visible
appearance by which the bodily sense was informed, from the similitude
of it, which was wrought in the sense when informed in order to
produce vision (otherwise they had been so united as to be thought
altogether one and the same); so, although that phantasy also, which
arises from the mind thinking of the appearance of a body that it has
seen, consists of the similitude of the body which the memory retains,
together with that which is thence formed in the eye of the mind that
recollects; yet it so seems to be one and single, that it can only be
discovered to be two by the judgment of reason, by which we understand
that which remains in the memory, even when we think it from some
other source, to be a different thing from that which is brought into
being when we remember, that is, come back again to the memory, and
there find the same appearance. And if this were not now there, we
should say that we had so forgotten as to be altogether unable to
recollect. And if the eye of him who recollects were not informed from
that thing which was in the memory, the vision of the thinker could in
no way take place; but the conjunction of both, that is, of that which
the memory retains, and of that which is thence expressed so as to
inform the eye of him who recollects, makes them appear as if they
were one, because they are exceedingly like. But when the eye of the
concipient is turned away thence, and has ceased to look at that which
was perceived in the memory, then nothing of the form that was
impressed thereon will remain in that eye, and it will be informed by
that to which it had again been turned, so as to bring about another
conception. Yet that remains which it has left in the memory, to which
it may again be turned when we recollect it, and being turned thereto
may be informed by it, and become one with that whence it is informed.
Footnotes
[732] Coactus
[733] Cogitatio
Chapter 4.--How This Unity Comes to Pass.
7. But if that will which moves to and fro, hither and thither, the
eye that is to be informed, and unites it when formed, shall have
wholly converged to the inward phantasy, and shall have absolutely
turned the mind's eye from the presence of the bodies which lie around
the senses, and from the very bodily senses themselves, and shall have
wholly turned it to that image, which is perceived within; then so
exact a likeness of the bodily species expressed from the memory is
presented, that not even reason itself is permitted to discern whether
the body itself is seen without, or only something of the kind thought
of within. For men sometimes either allured or frightened by over-much
thinking of visible things, have even suddenly uttered words
accordingly, as if in real fact they were engaged in the very midst of
such actions or sufferings. And I remember some one telling me that he
was wont to perceive in thought, so distinct and as it were solid, a
form of a female body, as to be moved, as though it were a reality.
Such power has the soul over its own body, and such influence has it
in turning and changing the quality of its [corporeal] garment; just
as a man may be affected when clothed, to whom his clothing sticks. It
is the same kind of affection, too, with which we are beguiled through
imaginations in sleep. But it makes a very great difference, whether
the senses of the body are lulled to torpor, as in the case of
sleepers, or disturbed from their inward structure, as in the case of
madmen, or distracted in some other mode, as in that of diviners or
prophets; and so from one or other of these causes, the intention of
the mind is forced by a kind of necessity upon those images which
occur to it, either from memory, or by some other hidden force through
certain spiritual commixtures of a similarly spiritual substance: or
whether, as sometimes happens to people in health and awake, that the
will occupied by thought turns itself away from the senses, and so
informs the eye of the mind by various images of sensible things, as
though those sensible things themselves were actually perceived. But
these impressions of images not only take place when the will is
directed upon such things by desiring them, but also when, in order to
avoid and guard against them, the mind is carried away to look upon
these very thing so as to flee from them. And hence, not only desire,
but fear, causes both the bodily eye to be informed by the sensible
things themselves, and the mental eye (acies) by the images of those
sensible things. Accordingly, the more vehement has been either fear
or desire, the more distinctly is the eye informed, whether in the
case of him who [sensuously] perceives by means of the body that which
lies close to him in place, or in the case of him who conceives from
the image of the body which is contained in the memory. What then a
body in place is to the bodily sense, that, the similitude of a body
in memory is to the eye of the mind; and what the vision of one who
looks at a thing is to that appearance of the body from which the
sense is informed, that, the vision of a concipient is to the image of
the body established in the memory, from which the eye of the mind is
informed; and what the intention of the will is towards a body seen
and the vision to be combined with it, in order that a certain unity
of three things may therein take place, although their nature is
diverse, that, the same intention of the will is towards combining the
image of the body which is in the memory, and the vision of the
concipient, that is, the form which the eye of the mind has taken in
returning to the memory, in order that here too a certain unity may
take place of three things, not now distinguished by diversity of
nature, but of one and the same substance; because this whole is
within, and the whole is one mind.
Chapter 5.--The Trinity of the Outer Man, or of External Vision, is
Not an Image of God. The Likeness of God is Desired Even in Sins. In
External Vision the Form of the Corporeal Thing is as It Were the
Parent, Vision the Offspring; But the Will that Unites These Suggests
the Holy Spirit.
8. But as, when [both] the form and species of a body have perished,
the will cannot recall to it the sense of perceiving; so, when the
image which memory bears is blotted out by forgetfulness, the will
will be unable to force back the eye of the mind by recollection, so
as to be formed thereby. But because the mind has great power to
imagine not only things forgotten, but also things that it never saw,
or experienced, either by increasing, or diminishing, or changing, or
compounding, after its pleasure, those which have not dropped out of
its remembrance, it often imagines things to be such as either it
knows they are not, or does not know that they are. And in this case
we have to take care, lest it either speak falsely that it may
deceive, or hold an opinion so as to be deceived. And if it avoid
these two evils, then imagined phantasms do not hinder it: just as
sensible things experienced or retained by memory do not hinder it, if
they are neither passionately sought for when pleasant, nor basely
shunned when unpleasant. But when the will leaves better things, and
greedily wallows in these, then it becomes unclean; and they are so
thought of hurtfully, when they are present, and also more hurtfully
when they are absent. And he therefore lives badly and degenerately
who lives according to the trinity of the outer man; because it is the
purpose of using things sensible and corporeal, that has begotten also
that trinity, which although it imagines within, yet imagines things
without. For no one could use those things even well, unless the
images of things perceived by the senses were retained in the memory.
And unless the will for the greatest part dwells in the higher and
interior things, and unless that will itself, which is accommodated
either to bodies without, or to the images of them within, refers
whatever it receives in them to a better and truer life, and rests in
that end by gazing at which it judges that those things ought to be
done; what else do we do, but that which the apostle prohibits us from
doing, when he says, "Be not conformed to this world"? [734] And
therefore that trinity is not an image of God since it is produced in
the mind itself through the bodily sense, from the lowest, that is,
the corporeal creature, than which the mind is higher. Yet neither is
it altogether dissimilar: for what is there that has not a likeness of
God, in proportion to its kind and measure, seeing that God made all
things very good, [735] and for no other reason except that He Himself
is supremely good? In so far, therefore, as anything that is, is good,
in so far plainly it has still some likeness of the supreme good, at
however great a distance; and if a natural likeness, then certainly a
right and well-ordered one; but if a faulty likeness, then certainly a
debased and perverse one. For even souls in their very sins strive
after nothing else but some kind of likeness of God, in a proud and
preposterous, and, so to say, slavish liberty. So neither could our
first parents have been persuaded to sin unless it had been said, "Ye
shall be as gods." [736] No doubt every thing in the creatures which
is in any way like God, is not also to be called His image; but that
alone than which He Himself alone is higher. For that only is in all
points copied from Him, between which and Himself no nature is
interposed.
9. Of that vision then; that is, of the form which is wrought in the
sense of him who sees; the form of the bodily thing from which it is
wrought, is, as it were, the parent. But it is not a true parent;
whence neither is that a true offspring; for it is not altogether born
therefrom, since something else is applied to the bodily thing in
order that it may be formed from it, namely, the sense of him who
sees. And for this reason, to love this is to be estranged. [737]
Therefore the will which unites both, viz. the quasi-parent and the
quasi-child, is more spiritual than either of them. For that bodily
thing which is discerned, is not spiritual at all. But the vision
which comes into existence in the sense, has something spiritual
mingled with it, since it cannot come into existence without the soul.
But it is not wholly spiritual; since that which is formed is a sense
of the body. Therefore the will which unites both is confessedly more
spiritual, as I have said; and so it begins to suggest (insinuare), as
it were, the person of the Spirit in the Trinity. But it belongs more
to the sense that is formed, than to the bodily thing whence it is
formed. For the sense and will of an animate being belongs to the
soul, not to the stone or other bodily thing that is seen. It does not
therefore proceed from that bodily thing as from a parent; yet neither
does it proceed from that other as it were offspring, namely, the
vision and form that is in the sense. For the will existed before the
vision came to pass, which will applied the sense that was to be
formed to the bodily thing that was to be discerned; but it was not
yet satisfied. For how could that which was not yet seen satisfy? And
satisfaction means a will that rests content. And, therefore, we can
neither call the will the quasi-offspring of vision, since it existed
before vision; nor the quasi-parent, since that vision was not formed
and expressed from the will, but from the bodily thing that was seen.
Footnotes
[734] Rom. xii. 2
[735] Ecclus. xxxix. 16
[736] Gen. iii. 5
[737] Vid. Retract. Bk. II. c. 15, where Augustin adds that it is
possible to love the bodily species to the praise of the Creator, in
which case there is no "estrangement."
Chapter 6.--Of What Kind We are to Reckon the Rest (Requies), and End
(Finis), of the Will in Vision.
10. Perhaps we can rightly call vision the end and rest of the will,
only with respect to this one object [namely, the bodily thing that is
visible]. For it will not will nothing else merely because it sees
something which it is now willing. It is not therefore the whole will
itself of the man, of which the end is nothing else than blessedness;
but the will provisionally directed to this one object, which has as
its end in seeing, nothing but vision, whether it refer the thing seen
to any other thing or not. For if it does not refer the vision to
anything further, but wills only to see this, there can be no question
made about showing that the end of the will is the vision; for it is
manifest. But if it does refer it to anything further, then certainly
it does will something else, and it will not be now a will merely to
see; or if to see, not one to see the particular thing. Just as, if
any one wished to see the scar, that from thence he might learn that
there had been a wound; or wished to see the window, that through the
window he might see the passers-by: all these and other such acts of
will have their own proper [proximate] ends, which are referred to
that [final] end of the will by which we will to live blessedly, and
to attain to that life which is not referred to anything else, but
suffices of itself to him who loves it. The will then to see, has as
its end vision; and the will to see this particular thing, has as its
end the vision of this particular thing. Therefore the will to see the
scar, desires its own end, that is, the vision of the scar, and does
not reach beyond it; for the will to prove that there had been a
wound, is a distinct will, although dependent upon that, of which the
end also is to prove that there had been a wound. And the will to see
the window, has as its end the vision of the window; for that is
another and further will which depends upon it, viz. to see the
passers-by through the window, of which also the end is the vision of
the passers-by. But all the several wills that are bound to each
other, are at once right, if that one is good, to which all are
referred; and if that is bad, then all are bad. And so the connected
series of right wills is a sort of road which consists as it were of
certain steps, whereby to ascend to blessedness; but the entanglement
of depraved and distorted wills is a bond by which he will be bound
who thus acts, so as to be cast into outer darkness. [738] Blessed
therefore are they who in act and character sing the song of the steps
[degrees]; [739] and woe to those that draw sin, as it were a long
rope. [740] And it is just the same to speak of the will being in
repose, which we call its end, if it is still referred to something
further, as if we should say that the foot is at rest in walking, when
it is placed there, whence yet another foot may be planted in the
direction of the man's steps. But if something so satisfies, that the
will acquiesces in it with a certain delight; it is nevertheless not
yet that to which the man ultimately tends; but this too is referred
to something further, so as to be regarded not as the native country
of a citizen, but as a place of refreshment, or even of stopping, for
a traveller.
Footnotes
[738] Matt. xxii. 13
[739] Psalms cxx., and following.
[740] Isa. v. 18
Chapter 7.--There is Another Trinity in the Memory of Him Who Thinks
Over Again What He Has Seen.
11. But yet again, take the case of another trinity, more inward
indeed than that which is in things sensible, and in the senses, but
which is yet conceived from thence; while now it is no longer the
sense of the body that is informed from the body, but the eye of the
mind that is informed from the memory, since the species of the body
which we perceived from without has inhered in the memory itself. And
that species, which is in the memory, we call the quasi-parent of that
which is wrought in the phantasy of one who conceives. For it was in
the memory also, before we conceived it, just as the body was in place
also before we [sensuously] perceived it, in order that vision might
take place. But when it is conceived, then from that form which the
memory retains, there is copied in the mind's eye (acie) of him who
conceives, and by remembrance is formed, that species, which is the
quasi-offspring of that which the memory retains. But neither is the
one a true parent, nor the other a true offspring. For the mind's
vision which is formed from memory when we think anything by
recollection, does not proceed from that species which we remember as
seen; since we could not indeed have remembered those things, unless
we had seen them; yet the mind's eye, which is informed by the
recollection, existed also before we saw the body that we remember;
and therefore how much more before we committed it to memory? Although
therefore the form which is wrought in the mind's eye of him who
remembers, is wrought from that form which is in the memory; yet the
mind's eye itself does not exist from thence, but existed before it.
And it follows, that if the one is not a true parent, neither is the
other a true offspring. But both that quasi-parent and that
quasi-offspring suggest something, whence the inner and truer things
may appear more practically and more certainly.
12. Further, it is more difficult to discern clearly, whether the will
which connects the vision to the memory is not either the parent or
the offspring of some one of them; and the likeness and equality of
the same nature and substance cause this difficulty of distinguishing.
For it is not possible to do in this case, as with the sense that is
formed from without (which is easily discerned from the sensible body,
and again the will from both), on account of the difference of nature
which is mutually in all three, and of which we have treated
sufficiently above. For although this trinity, of which we at present
speak, is introduced into the mind from without; yet it is transacted
within, and there is no part of it outside of the nature of the mind
itself. In what way, then, can it be demonstrated that the will is
neither the quasi-parent, nor the quasi-offspring, either of the
corporeal likeness which is contained in the memory, or of that which
is copied thence in recollecting; when it so unites both in the act of
conceiving, as that they appear singly as one, and cannot be discerned
except by reason? It is then first to be considered that there cannot
be any will to remember, unless we retain in the recesses of the
memory either the whole, or some part, of that thing which we wish to
remember. For the very will to remember cannot arise in the case of a
thing which we have forgotten altogether and absolutely; since we have
already remembered that the thing which we wish to remember is or has
been, in our memory. For example, if I wish to remember what I supped
on yesterday, either I have already remembered that I did sup, or if
not yet this, at least I have remembered something about that time
itself, if nothing else; at all events, I have remembered yesterday,
and that part of yesterday in which people usually sup, and what
supping is. For if I had not remembered anything at all of this kind,
I could not wish to remember what I supped on yesterday. Whence we may
perceive that the will of remembering proceeds, indeed, from those
things which are retained in the memory, with the addition also of
those which, by the act of discerning, are copied thence through
recollection; that is, from the combination of something which we have
remembered, and of the vision which was thence wrought, when we
remembered, in the mind's eye of him who thinks. But the will itself
which unites both requires also some other thing, which is, as it
were, close at hand, and adjacent to him who remembers. There are,
then, as many trinities of this kind as there are remembrances;
because there is no one of them wherein there are not these three
things, viz. that which was stored up in the memory also before it was
thought, and that which takes place in the conception when this is
discerned, and the will that unites both, and from both and itself as
a third, completes one single thing. Or is it rather that we so
recognize some one trinity in this kind, as that we are to speak
generally, of whatever corporeal species lie hidden in the memory, as
of a single unity, and again of the general vision of the mind which
remembers and conceives such things, as of a single unity, to the
combination of which two there is to be joined as a third the will
that combines them, that this whole may be a certain unity made up
from three?
Chapter 8.--Different Modes of Conceiving.
But since the eye of the mind cannot look at all things together, in
one glance, which the memory retains, these trinities of thought
alternate in a series of withdrawals and successions, and so that
trinity becomes most innumerably numerous; and yet not infinite, if it
pass not beyond the number of things stored up in the memory. For,
although we begin to reckon from the earliest perception which any one
has of material things through any bodily sense, and even take in also
those things which he has forgotten, yet the number would undoubtedly
be certain and determined, although innumerable. For we not only call
infinite things innumerable, but also those, which, although finite,
exceed any one's power of reckoning.
13. But we can hence perceive a little more clearly that what the
memory stores up and retains is a different thing from that which is
thence copied in the conception of the man who remembers, although,
when both are combined together, they appear to be one and the same;
because we can only remember just as many species of bodies as we have
actually seen, and so great, and such, as we have actually seen; for
the mind imbibes them into the memory from the bodily sense; whereas
the things seen in conception, although drawn from those things which
are in the memory, yet are multiplied and varied innumerably, and
altogether without end. For I remember, no doubt, but one sun, because
according to the fact, I have seen but one; but if I please, I
conceive of two, or three, or as many as I will; but the vision of my
mind, when I conceive of many, is formed from the same memory by which
I remember one. And I remember it just as large as I saw it. For if I
remember it as larger or smaller than I saw it, then I no longer
remember what I saw, and so I do not remember it. But because I
remember it, I remember it as large as I saw it; yet I conceive of it
as greater or as less according to my will. And I remember it as I saw
it; but I conceive of it as running its course as I will, and as
standing still where I will, and as coming whence I will, and whither
I will. For it is in my power to conceive of it as square, although I
remember it as round; and again, of what color I please, although I
have never seen, and therefore do not remember, a green sun; and as
the sun, so all other things. But owing to the corporeal and sensible
nature of these forms of things, the mind falls into error when it
imagines them to exist without, in the same mode in which it conceives
them within, either when they have already ceased to exist without,
but are still retained in the memory, or when in any other way also,
that which we remember is formed in the mind, not by faithful
recollection, but after the variations of thought.
14. Yet it very often happens that we believe also a true narrative,
told us by others, of things which the narrators have themselves
perceived by their senses. And in this case, when we conceive the
things narrated to us, as we hear them, the eye of the mind does not
seem to be turned back to the memory, in order to bring up visions in
our thoughts; for we do not conceive these things from our own
recollection, but upon the narration of another; and that trinity does
not here seem to come to its completion, which is made when the
species lying hid in the memory, and the vision of the man that
remembers, are combined by will as a third. For I do not conceive that
which lay hid in my memory, but that which I hear, when anything is
narrated to me. I am not speaking of the words themselves of the
speaker, lest any one should suppose that I have gone off to that
other trinity, which is transacted without, in sensible things, or in
the senses: but I am conceiving of those species of material things,
which the narrator signifies to me by words and sounds; which species
certainly I conceive of not by remembering, but by hearing. But if we
consider the matter more carefully, even in this case, the limit of
the memory is not overstepped. For I could not even understand the
narrator, if I did not remember generically the individual things of
which he speaks, even although I then hear them for the first time as
connected together in one tale. For he who, for instance, describes to
me some mountain stripped of timber, and clothed with olive trees,
describes it to me who remembers the species both of mountains, and of
timber, and of olive trees; and if I had forgotten these, I should not
know at all of what he was speaking, and therefore could not conceive
that description. And so it comes to pass, that every one who
conceives things corporeal, whether he himself imagine anything, or
hear, or read, either a narrative of things past, or a foretelling of
things future, has recourse to his memory, and finds there the limit
and measure of all the forms at which he gazes in his thought. For no
one can conceive at all, either a color or a form of body, which he
never saw, or a sound which he never heard, or a flavor which he never
tasted, or a scent which he never smelt, or any touch of a corporeal
thing which he never felt. But if no one conceives anything corporeal
except what he has [sensuously] perceived, because no one remembers
anything corporeal except what he has thus perceived, then, as is the
limit of perceiving in bodies, so is the limit of thinking in the
memory. For the sense receives the species from that body which we
perceive, and the memory from the sense; but the mental eye of the
concipient, from the memory.
15. Further, as the will applies the sense to the bodily object, so it
applies the memory to the sense, and the eye of the mind of the
concipient to the memory. But that which harmonizes those things and
unites them, itself also disjoins and separates them, that is, the
will. But it separates the bodily senses from the bodies that are to
be perceived, by movement of the body, either to hinder our perceiving
the thing, or that we may cease to perceive it: as when we avert our
eyes from that which we are unwilling to see, or shut them; so, again,
the ears from sounds, or the nostrils from smells. So also we turn
away from tastes, either by shutting the mouth, or by casting the
thing out of the mouth. In touch, also, we either remove the bodily
thing, that we may not touch what we do not wish, or if we were
already touching it, we fling or push it away. Thus the will acts by
movement of the body, so that the bodily sense shall not be joined to
the sensible things. And it does this according to its power; for when
it endures hardship in so doing, on account of the condition of
slavish mortality, then torment is the result, in such wise that
nothing remains to the will save endurance. But the will averts the
memory from the sense; when, through its being intent on something
else, it does not suffer things present to cleave to it. As any one
may see, when often we do not seem to ourselves to have heard some one
who was speaking to us, because we were thinking of something else.
But this is a mistake; for we did hear, but we do not remember,
because the words of the speaker presently slipped out of the
perception of our ears, through the bidding of the will being diverted
elsewhere, by which they are usually fixed in the memory. Therefore,
we should say more accurately in such a case, we do not remember,
than, we did not hear; for it happens even in reading, and to myself
very frequently, that when I have read through a page or an epistle, I
do not know what I have read, and I begin it again. For the purpose of
the will being fixed on something else, the memory was not so applied
to the bodily sense, as the sense itself was applied to the letters.
So, too, any one who walks with the will intent on something else,
does not know where he has got to; for if he had not seen, he would
not have walked thither, or would have felt his way in walking with
greater attention, especially if he was passing through a place he did
not know; yet, because he walked easily, certainly he saw; but because
the memory was not applied to the sense itself in the same way as the
sense of the eyes was applied to the places through which he was
passing, he could not remember at all even the last thing he saw. Now,
to will to turn away the eye of the mind from that which is in the
memory, is nothing else but not to think thereupon.
Chapter 9.--Species is Produced by Species in Succession.
16. In this arrangement, then, while we begin from the bodily species
and arrive finally at the species which comes to be in the intuition
(contuitu) of the concipient, we find four species born, as it were,
step by step one from the other, the second from the first, the third
from the second, the fourth from the third: since from the species of
the body itself, there arises that which comes to be in the sense of
the percipient; and from this, that which comes to be in the memory;
and from this, that which comes to be in the mind's eye of the
concipient. And the will, therefore, thrice combines as it were parent
with offspring: first the species of the body with that to which it
gives birth in the sense of the body; and that again with that which
from it comes to be in the memory; and this also, thirdly, with that
which is born from it in the intuition of the concipient's mind. But
the intermediate combination which is the second, although it is
nearer to the first, is yet not so like the first as the third is. For
there are two kinds of vision, the one of [sensuous] perception
(sentientis), the other of conception (cogitantis). But in order that
the vision of conception may come to be, there is wrought for the
purpose, in the memory, from the vision of [sensuous] perception
something like it, to which the eye of the mind may turn itself in
conceiving, as the glance (acies) of the eyes turns itself in
[sensuously] perceiving to the bodily object. I have, therefore,
chosen to put forward two trinities in this kind: one when the vision
of [sensuous] perception is formed from the bodily object, the other
when the vision of conception is formed from the memory. But I have
refrained from commending an intermediate one; because we do not
commonly call it vision, when the form which comes to be in the sense
of him who perceives, is entrusted to the memory. Yet in all cases the
will does not appear unless as the combiner as it were of parent and
offspring; and so, proceed from whence it may, it can be called
neither parent nor offspring. [741]
Footnotes
[741] [Augustin's map of consciousness is as follows: (1). The
corporeal species=the external object (outward appearance). (2). The
sensible species=the sensation (appearance for the sense). (3). The
mental species in its first form=present perception. (4). The mental
species in its second form=remembered perception. These three
"species" or appearances of the object: namely, corporeal, sensible,
and mental, according to him, are combined in one synthesis with the
object by the operation of the will. By "will," he does not mean
distinct and separate volitions: but the spontaneity of the ego--what
Kant denominates the mechanism of the understanding, seen in the
spontaneous employment of the categories of thought, as the mind
ascends from empirical sensation to rational conception. The English
translator has failed to make clear the sharply defined psychology of
these chapters, by loosely rendering "sentire," "to perceive," and
"cogitare" to think.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 10.--The Imagination Also Adds Even to Things We Have Not
Seen, Those Things Which We Have Seen Elsewhere.
17. But if we do not remember except what we have [sensuously]
perceived, nor conceive except what we remember; why do we often
conceive things that are false, when certainly we do not remember
falsely those things which we have perceived, unless it be because
that will (which I have already taken pains to show as much as I can
to be the uniter and the separater of things of this kind) leads the
vision of the conceiver that is to be formed, after its own will and
pleasure, through the hidden stores of the memory; and, in order to
conceive [imagine] those things which we do not remember, impels it to
take one thing from hence, and another from thence, from those which
we do remember; and these things combining into one vision make
something which is called false, because it either does not exist
externally in the nature of corporeal things, or does not seem copied
from the memory, in that we do not remember that we ever saw such a
thing. For who ever saw a black swan? And therefore no one remembers a
black swan; yet who is there that cannot conceive it? For it is easy
to apply to that shape which we have come to know by seeing it, a
black color, which we have not the less seen in other bodies; and
because we have seen both, we remember both. Neither do I remember a
bird with four feet, because I never saw one; but I contemplate such a
phantasy very easily, by adding to some winged shape such as I have
seen, two other feet, such as I have likewise seen. [742] And
therefore, in conceiving conjointly, what we remember to have seen
singly, we seem not to conceive that which we remember; while we
really do this under the law of the memory, whence we take everything
which we join together after our own pleasure in manifold and diverse
ways. For we do not conceive even the very magnitudes of bodies, which
magnitudes we never saw, without help of the memory; for the measure
of space to which our gaze commonly reaches through the magnitude of
the world, is the measure also to which we enlarge the bulk of bodies,
whatever they may be, when we conceive them as great as we can. And
reason, indeed, proceeds still beyond, but phantasy does not follow
her; as when reason announces the infinity of number also, which no
vision of him who conceives according to corporeal things can
apprehend. The same reason also teaches that the most minute atoms are
infinitely divisible; yet when we have come to those slight and minute
particles which we remember to have seen, then we can no longer behold
phantasms more slender and more minute, although reason does not cease
to continue to divide them. So we conceive no corporeal things, except
either those we remember, or from those things which we remember.
Footnotes
[742] Vid. Retract. 11. xv. 2. [Augustin here says that when he wrote
the above, he forgot what is said in Leviticus xi. 20, of "fowls that
creep, going upon all four, which have legs above their feet to leap
withal upon the earth."--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 11.--Number, Weight, Measure.
18. But because those things which are impressed on the memory singly,
can be conceived according to number, measure seems to belong to the
memory, but number to the vision; because, although the multiplicity
of such visions is innumerable, yet a limit not to be transgressed is
prescribed for each in the memory. Therefore, measure appears in the
memory, number in the vision of things: as there is some measure in
visible bodies themselves, to which measure the sense of those who see
is most numerously adjusted, and from one visible object is formed the
vision of many beholders, so that even a single person sees commonly a
single thing under a double appearance, on account of the number of
his two eyes, as we have laid down above. Therefore there is some
measure in those things whence visions are copied, but in the visions
themselves there is number. But the will which unites and regulates
these things, and combines them into a certain unity, and does not
quietly rest its desire of [sensuously] perceiving or of conceiving,
except in those things from whence the visions are formed, resembles
weight. And therefore I would just notice by way of anticipation these
three things, measure, number, weight, which are to be perceived in
all other things also. In the meantime, I have now shown as much as I
can, and to whom I can, that the will is the uniter of the visible
thing and of the vision; as it were, of parent and of offspring;
whether in [sensuous] perception or in conception, and that it cannot
be called either parent or offspring. Wherefore time admonishes us to
seek for this same trinity in the inner man, and to strive to pass
inwards from that animal and carnal and (as he is called) outward man,
of whom I have so long spoken. And here we hope to be able to find an
image of God according to the Trinity, He Himself helping our efforts,
who as things themselves show, and as Holy Scripture also witnesses,
has regulated all things in measure, and number, and weight. [743]
Footnotes
[743] Wisd. xi. 21
.
Book XII.
Commencing with a distinction between wisdom and knowledge, points out
a kind of trinity, of a peculiar sort, in that which is properly
called knowledge, and which is the lower of the two; and this trinity,
although it certainly pertains to the inner man, is still not yet to
be called or thought an image of God.
Chapter 1.--Of What Kind are the Outer and the Inner Man.
1. Come now, and let us see where lies, as it were, the boundary line
between the outer and inner man. For whatever we have in the mind
common with the beasts, thus much is rightly said to belong to the
outer man. For the outer man is not to be considered to be the body
only, but with the addition also of a certain peculiar life of the
body, whence the structure of the body derives its vigor, and all the
senses with which he is equipped for the perception of outward things;
and when the images of these outward things already perceived, that
have been fixed in the memory, are seen again by recollection, it is
still a matter pertaining to the outer man. And in all these things we
do not differ from the beasts, except that in shape of body we are not
prone, but upright. And we are admonished through this, by Him who
made us, not to be like the beasts in that which is our better
part--that is, the mind--while we differ from them by the uprightness
of the body. Not that we are to throw our mind into those bodily
things which are exalted; for to seek rest for the will, even in such
things, is to prostrate the mind. But as the body is naturally raised
upright to those bodily things which are most elevated, that is, to
things celestial; so the mind, which is a spiritual substance, must be
raised upright to those things which are most elevated in spiritual
things, not by the elation of pride, but by the dutifulness of
righteousness.
Chapter 2.--Man Alone of Animate Creatures Perceives the Eternal
Reasons of Things Pertaining to the Body.
2. And the beasts, too, are able both to perceive things corporeal
from without, through the senses of the body, and to fix them in the
memory, and remember them, and in them to seek after things suitable,
and shun things inconvenient. But to note these things, and to retain
them not only as caught up naturally but also as deliberately
committed to memory, and to imprint them again by recollection and
conception when now just slipping away into forgetfulness; in order
that as conception is formed from that which the memory contains, so
also the contents themselves of the memory may be fixed firmly by
thought: to combine again imaginary objects of sight, by taking this
or that of what the memory remembers, and, as it were, tacking them to
one another: to examine after what manner it is that in this kind
things like the true are to be distinguished from the true, and this
not in things spiritual, but in corporeal things themselves;--these
acts, and the like, although performed in reference to things
sensible, and those which the mind has deduced through the bodily
senses, yet, as they are combined with reason, so are not common to
men and beasts. But it is the part of the higher reason to judge of
these corporeal things according to incorporeal and eternal reasons;
which, unless they were above the human mind, would certainly not be
unchangeable; and yet, unless something of our own were subjoined to
them, we should not be able to employ them as our measures by which to
judge of corporeal things. But we judge of corporeal things from the
rule of dimensions and figures, which the mind knows to remain
unchangeably. [744]
Footnotes
[744] [The distinction drawn here is between that low form of
intelligence which exists in the brute, and that high form
characteristic of man. In the Kantian nomenclature, the brute has
understanding, but unenlightened by reason; either theoretical or
practical. He has intelligence, but not as modified by the forms of
space and time and the categories of quantity, quality, relation etc.;
and still less as modified and exalted by the ideas of reason--namely,
the mathematical ideas, and the moral ideas of God, freedom, and
immortality. The animal has no rational intelligence. He has mere
understanding without reason.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 3.--The Higher Reason Which Belongs to Contemplation, and the
Lower Which Belongs to Action, are in One Mind.
3. But that of our own which thus has to do with the handling of
corporeal and temporal things, is indeed rational, in that it is not
common to us with the beasts; but it is drawn, as it were, out of that
rational substance of our mind, by which we depend upon and cleave to
the intelligible and unchangeable truth, and which is deputed to
handle and direct the inferior things. For as among all the beasts
there was not found for the man a help like unto him, unless one were
taken from himself, and formed to be his consort: so for that mind, by
which we consult the supernal and inward truth, there is no like help
for such employment as man's nature requires among things corporeal
out of those parts of the soul which we have in common with the
beasts. And so a certain part of our reason, not separated so as to
sever unity, but, as it were, diverted so as to be a help to
fellowship, is parted off for the performing of its proper work. And
as the twain is one flesh in the case of male and female, so in the
mind one nature embraces our intellect and action, or our counsel and
performance, or our reason and rational appetite, or whatever other
more significant terms there may be by which to express them; so that,
as it was said of the former, "And they two shall be in one flesh,"
[745] it may be said of these, they two are in one mind.
Footnotes
[745] Gen. ii. 24
Chapter 4.--The Trinity and the Image of God is in that Part of the
Mind Alone Which Belongs to the Contemplation of Eternal Things.
4. When, therefore, we discuss the nature of the human mind, we
discuss a single subject, and do not double it into those two which I
have mentioned, except in respect to its functions. Therefore, when we
seek the trinity in the mind, we seek it in the whole mind, without
separating the action of the reason in things temporal from the
contemplation of things eternal, so as to have further to seek some
third thing, by which a trinity may be completed. But this trinity
must needs be so discovered in the whole nature of the mind, as that
even if action upon temporal things were to be withdrawn, for which
work that help is necessary, with a view to which some part of the
mind is diverted in order to deal with these inferior things, yet a
trinity would still be found in the one mind that is no where parted
off; and that when this distribution has been already made, not only a
trinity may be found, but also an image of God, in that alone which
belongs to the contemplation of eternal things; while in that other
which is diverted from it in the dealing with temporal things,
although there may be a trinity, yet there cannot be found an image of
God.
Chapter 5.--The Opinion Which Devises an Image of the Trinity in the
Marriage of Male and Female, and in Their Offspring.
5. Accordingly they do not seem to me to advance a probable opinion,
who lay it down that a trinity of the image of God in three persons,
so far as regards human nature, can so be discovered as to be
completed in the marriage of male and female and in their offspring;
in that the man himself, as it were, indicates the person of the
Father, but that which has so proceeded from him as to be born, that
of the Son; and so the third person as of the Spirit, is, they say,
the woman, who has so proceeded from the man as not herself to be
either son or daughter, [746] although it was by her conception that
the offspring was born. For the Lord hath said of the Holy Spirit that
He proceedeth from the Father, [747] and yet he is not a son. In this
erroneous opinion, then, the only point probably alleged, and indeed
sufficiently shown according to the faith of the Holy Scripture, is
this,--in the account of the original creation of the woman,--that
what so comes into existence from some person as to make another
person, cannot in every case be called a son; since the person of the
woman came into existence from the person of the man, and yet she is
not called his daughter. All the rest of this opinion is in truth so
absurd, nay indeed so false, that it is most easy to refute it. For I
pass over such a thing, as to think the Holy Spirit to be the mother
of the Son of God, and the wife of the Father; since perhaps it may be
answered that these things offend us in carnal things, because we
think of bodily conceptions and births. Although these very things
themselves are most chastely thought of by the pure, to whom all
things are pure; but to the defiled and unbelieving, of whom both the
mind and conscience are polluted, nothing is pure; [748] so that even
Christ, born of a virgin according to the flesh, is a stumbling-block
to some of them. But yet in the case of those supreme spiritual
things, after the likeness of which those kinds of the inferior
creature also are made although most remotely, and where there is
nothing that can be injured and nothing corruptible, nothing born in
time, nothing formed from that which is formless, or whatever like
expressions there may be; yet they ought not to disturb the sober
prudence of any one, lest in avoiding empty disgust he run into
pernicious error. Let him accustom himself so to find in corporeal
things the traces of things spiritual, that when he begins to ascend
upwards from thence, under the guidance of reason, in order to attain
to the unchangeable truth itself through which these things were made,
he may not draw with himself to things above what he despises in
things below. For no one ever blushed to choose for himself wisdom as
a wife, because the name of wife puts into a man's thoughts the
corruptible connection which consists in begetting children; or
because in truth wisdom itself is a woman in sex, since it is
expressed in both Greek and Latin tongues by a word of the feminine
gender.
Footnotes
[746] Gen. ii. 22
[747] John xv. 26
[748] Tit. i. 15
Chapter 6. --Why This Opinion is to Be Rejected.
6. We do not therefore reject this opinion, because we fear to think
of that holy and inviolable and unchangeable Love, as the spouse of
God the Father, existing as it does from Him, but not as an offspring
in order to beget the Word by which all things are made; but because
divine Scripture evidently shows it to be false. For God said, "Let us
make man in our image, after our likeness;" and a little after it is
said, "So God created man in the image of God." [749] Certainly, in
that it is of the plural number, the word "our" would not be rightly
used if man were made in the image of one person, whether of the
Father, or of the Son, or of the Holy Spirit; but because he was made
in the image of the Trinity, on that account it is said, "After our
image." But again, lest we should think that three Gods were to be
believed in the Trinity, whereas the same Trinity is one God, it is
said, "So God created man in the image of God," instead of saying, "In
His own image."
7. For such expressions are customary in the Scriptures; and yet some
persons, while maintaining the Catholic faith, do not carefully attend
to them, in such wise that they think the words, "God made man in the
image of God," to mean that the Father made man after the image of the
Son; and they thus desire to assert that the Son also is called God in
the divine Scriptures, as if there were not other most true and clear
proofs wherein the Son is called not only God, but also the true God.
For whilst they aim at explaining another difficulty in this text,
they become so entangled that they cannot extricate themselves. For if
the Father made man after the image of the Son, so that he is not the
image of the Father, but of the Son, then the Son is unlike the
Father. But if a pious faith teaches us, as it does, that the Son is
like the Father after an equality of essence, then that which is made
in the likeness of the Son must needs also be made in the likeness of
the Father. Further, if the Father made man not in His own image, but
in the image of His Son, why does He not say, "Let us make man after
Thy image and likeness," whereas He does say, "our;" unless it be
because the image of the Trinity was made in man, that in this way man
should be the image of the one true God, because the Trinity itself is
the one true God? Such expressions are innumerable in the Scriptures,
but it will suffice to have produced these. It is so said in the
Psalms, "Salvation belongeth unto the Lord; Thy blessing is upon Thy
people;" [750] as if the words were spoken to some one else, not to
Him of whom it had been said, "Salvation belongeth unto the Lord." And
again, "For by Thee," he says, "I shall be delivered from temptation,
and by hoping in my God I shall leap over the wall;" [751] as if he
said to some one else, "By Thee I shall be delivered from temptation."
And again, "In the heart of the king's enemies; whereby the people
fall under Thee;" [752] as if he were to say, in the heart of Thy
enemies. For he had said to that King, that is, to our Lord Jesus
Christ, "The people fall under Thee," whom he intended by the word
King, when he said, "In the heart of the king's enemies." Things of
this kind are found more rarely in the New Testament. But yet the
apostle says to the Romans, "Concerning His Son who was made to Him of
the seed of David according to the flesh, and declared to be the Son
of God with power, according to the spirit of holiness, by the
resurrection of the dead of Jesus Christ our Lord;" [753] as though he
were speaking above of some one else. For what is meant by the Son of
God declared by the resurrection of the dead of Jesus Christ, except
of the same Jesus Christ who was declared to be Son of God with power?
And as then in this passage, when we are told, "the Son of God with
power of Jesus Christ," or "the Son of God according to the spirit of
holiness of Jesus Christ," or "the Son of God by the resurrection of
the dead of Jesus Christ," whereas it might have been expressed in the
ordinary way, In His own power, or according to the spirit of His own
holiness, or by the resurrection of His dead, or of their dead: as, I
say, we are not compelled to understand another person, but one and
the same, that is, the person of the Son of God our Lord Jesus Christ;
so, when we are told that "God made man in the image of God," although
it might have been more usual to say, after His own image, yet we are
not compelled to understand any other person in the Trinity, but the
one and selfsame Trinity itself, who is one God, and after whose image
man is made.
8. And since the case stands thus, if we are to accept the same image
of the Trinity, as not in one, but in three human beings, father and
mother and son, then the man was not made after the image of God
before a wife was made for him, and before they procreated a son;
because there was not yet a trinity. Will any one say there was
already a trinity, because, although not yet in their proper form, yet
in their original nature, both the woman was already in the side of
the man, and the son in the loins of his father? Why then, when
Scripture had said, "God made man after the image of God," did it go
on to say, "God created him; male and female created He them: and God
blessed them"? [754] (Or if it is to be so divided, "And God created
man," so that thereupon is to be added, "in the image of God created
He him," and then subjoined in the third place, "male and female
created He them;" for some have feared to say, He made him male and
female, lest something monstrous, as it were, should be understood, as
are those whom they call hermaphrodites, although even so both might
be understood not falsely in the singular number, on account of that
which is said, "Two in one flesh.") Why then, as I began by saying, in
regard to the nature of man made after the image of God, does
Scripture specify nothing except male and female? Certainly, in order
to complete the image of the Trinity, it ought to have added also son,
although still placed in the loins of his father, as the woman was in
his side. Or was it perhaps that the woman also had been already made,
and that Scripture had combined in a short and comprehensive
statement, that of which it was going to explain afterwards more
carefully, how it was done; and that therefore a son could not be
mentioned, because no son was yet born? As if the Holy Spirit could
not have comprehended this, too, in that brief statement, while about
to narrate the birth of the son afterwards in its own place; as it
narrated afterwards in its own place, that the woman was taken from
the side of the man, [755] and yet has not omitted here to name her.
Footnotes
[749] Gen. i. 26, 27
[750] Ps. iii. 8
[751] Ps. xviii. 29
[752] Ps. xlv. 5
[753] Rom. i. 3, 4
[754] Gen. i. 27, 28
[755] Gen. ii. 24, 22
Chapter 7.--How Man is the Image of God. Whether the Woman is Not Also
the Image of God. How the Saying of the Apostle, that the Man is the
Image of God, But the Woman is the Glory of the Man, is to Be
Understood Figuratively and Mystically.
9. We ought not therefore so to understand that man is made in the
image of the supreme Trinity, that is, in the image of God, as that
the same image should be understood to be in three human beings;
especially when the apostle says that the man is the image of God, and
on that account removes the covering from his head, which he warns the
woman to use, speaking thus: "For a man indeed ought not to cover his
head, forasmuch as he is the image and glory of God; but the woman is
the glory of the man." What then shall we say to this? If the woman
fills up the image of the trinity after the measure of her own person,
why is the man still called that image after she has been taken out of
his side? Or if even one person of a human being out of three can be
called the image of God, as each person also is God in the supreme
Trinity itself, why is the woman also not the image of God? For she is
instructed for this very reason to cover her head, which he is
forbidden to do because he is the image of God. [756]
10. But we must notice how that which the apostle says, that not the
woman but the man is the image of God, is not contrary to that which
is written in Genesis, "God created man: in the image of God created
He him; male and female created He them: and He blessed them." For
this text says that human nature itself, which is complete [only] in
both sexes, was made in the image of God; and it does not separate the
woman from the image of God which it signifies. For after saying that
God made man in the image of God, "He created him," it says, "male and
female:" or at any rate, punctuating the words otherwise, "male and
female created He them." How then did the apostle tell us that the man
is the image of God, and therefore he is forbidden to cover his head;
but that the woman is not so, and therefore is commanded to cover
hers? Unless, forsooth, according to that which I have said already,
when I was treating of the nature of the human mind, that the woman
together with her own husband is the image of God, so that that whole
substance may be one image; but when she is referred separately to her
quality of help-meet, which regards the woman herself alone, then she
is not the image of God; but as regards the man alone, he is the image
of God as fully and completely as when the woman too is joined with
him in one. As we said of the nature of the human mind, that both in
the case when as a whole it contemplates the truth it is the image of
God; and in the case when anything is divided from it, and diverted in
order to the cognition of temporal things; nevertheless on that side
on which it beholds and consults truth, here also it is the image of
God, but on that side whereby it is directed to the cognition of the
lower things, it is not the image of God. And since it is so much the
more formed after the image of God, the more it has extended itself to
that which is eternal, and is on that account not to be restrained, so
as to withhold and refrain itself from thence; therefore the man ought
not to cover his head. But because too great a progression towards
inferior things is dangerous to that rational cognition that is
conversant with things corporeal and temporal; this ought to have
power on its head, which the covering indicates, by which it is
signified that it ought to be restrained. For a holy and pious meaning
is pleasing to the holy angels. [757] For God sees not after the way
of time, neither does anything new take place in His vision and
knowledge, when anything is done in time and transitorily, after the
way in which such things affect the senses, whether the carnal senses
of animals and men, or even the heavenly senses of the angels.
11. For that the Apostle Paul, when speaking outwardly of the sex of
male and female, figured the mystery of some more hidden truth, may be
understood from this, that when he says in another place that she is a
widow indeed who is desolate, without children and nephews, and yet
that she ought to trust in God, and to continue in prayers night and
day, [758] he here indicates, that the woman having been brought into
the transgression by being deceived, is brought to salvation by
child-bearing; and then he has added, "If they continue in faith, and
charity, and holiness, with sobriety." [759] As if it could possibly
hurt a good widow, if either she had not sons, or if those whom she
had did not choose to continue in good works. But because those things
which are called good works are, as it were, the sons of our life,
according to that sense of life in which it answers to the question,
What is a man's life? that is, How does he act in these temporal
things? which life the Greeks do not call xoe but bios; and because
these good works are chiefly performed in the way of offices of mercy,
while works of mercy are of no profit, either to Pagans, or to Jews
who do not believe in Christ, or to any heretics or schismstics
whatsoever in whom faith and charity and sober holiness are not found:
what the apostle meant to signify is plain, and in so far figuratively
and mystically, because he was speaking of covering the head of the
woman, which will remain mere empty words, unless referred to some
hidden sacrament.
12. For, as not only most true reason but also the authority of the
apostle himself declares, man was not made in the image of God
according to the shape of his body, but according to his rational
mind. For the thought is a debased and empty one, which holds God to
be circumscribed and limited by the lineaments of bodily members. But
further, does not the same blessed apostle say, "Be renewed in the
spirit of your mind, and put on the new man, which is created after
God;" [760] and in another place more clearly, "Putting off the old
man," he says, "with his deeds; put on the new man, which is renewed
to the knowledge of God after the image of Him that created him?"
[761] If, then, we are renewed in the spirit of our mind, and he is
the new man who is renewed to the knowledge of God after the image of
Him that created him; no one can doubt, that man was made after the
image of Him that created him, not according to the body, nor
indiscriminately according to any part of the mind, but according to
the rational mind, wherein the knowledge of God can exist. And it is
according to this renewal, also, that we are made sons of God by the
baptism of Christ; and putting on the new man, certainly put on Christ
through faith. Who is there, then, who will hold women to be alien
from this fellowship, whereas they are fellow-heirs of grace with us;
and whereas in another place the same apostle says, "For ye are all
the children of God by faith in Christ Jesus; for as many as have been
baptized into Christ have put on Christ: there is neither Jew nor
Greek, there is neither bond nor free, there is neither male nor
female; for ye are all one in Christ Jesus?" [762] Pray, have faithful
women then lost their bodily sex? But because they are there renewed
after the image of God, where there is no sex; man is there made after
the image of God, where there is no sex, that is, in the spirit of his
mind. Why, then, is the man on that account not bound to cover his
head, because he is the image and glory of God, while the woman is
bound to do so, because she is the glory of the man; as though the
woman were not renewed in the spirit of her mind, which spirit is
renewed to the knowledge of God after the image of Him who created
him? But because she differs from the man in bodily sex, it was
possible rightly to represent under her bodily covering that part of
the reason which is diverted to the government of temporal things; so
that the image of God may remain on that side of the mind of man on
which it cleaves to the beholding or the consulting of the eternal
reasons of things; and this, it is clear, not men only, but also women
have.
Footnotes
[756] 1 Cor. xi. 7, 5
[757] 1 Cor. xi. 10
[758] 1 Tim. v. 5
[759] 1 Tim. ii. 15
[760] Eph. iv. 23, 24
[761] Col. iii. 9, 10
[762] Gal. iii. 26-28
Chapter 8.--Turning Aside from the Image of God.
13. A common nature, therefore, is recognized in their minds, but in
their bodies a division of that one mind itself is figured. As we
ascend, then, by certain steps of thought within, along the succession
of the parts of the mind, there where something first meets us which
is not common to ourselves with the beasts reason begins, so that here
the inner man can now be recognized. And if this inner man himself,
through that reason to which the administering of things temporal has
been delegated, slips on too far by over-much progress into outward
things, that which is his head moreover consenting, that is, the (so
to call it) masculine part which presides in the watch-tower of
counsel not restraining or bridling it: then he waxeth old because of
all his enemies, [763] viz. the demons with their prince the devil,
who are envious of virtue; and that vision of eternal things is
withdrawn also from the head himself, eating with his spouse that
which was forbidden, so that the light of his eyes is gone from him;
[764] and so both being naked from that enlightenment of truth, and
with the eyes of their conscience opened to behold how they were left
shameful and unseemly, like the leaves of sweet fruits, but without
the fruits themselves, they so weave together good words without the
fruit of good works, as while living wickedly to cover over their
disgrace as it were by speaking well. [765]
Footnotes
[763] Ps. vi. 7
[764] Ps. xxxviii. 10
[765] Gen. iii. 4
Chapter 9.--The Same Argument is Continued.
14. For the soul loving its own power, slips onwards from the whole
which is common, to a part, which belongs especially to itself. And
that apostatizing pride, which is called "the beginning of sin," [766]
whereas it might have been most excellently governed by the laws of
God, if it had followed Him as its ruler in the universal creature, by
seeking something more than the whole, and struggling to govern this
by a law of its own, is thrust on, since nothing is more than the
whole, into caring for a part; and thus by lusting after something
more, is made less; whence also covetousness is called "the root of
all evil." [767] And it administers that whole, wherein it strives to
do something of its own against the laws by which the whole is
governed, by its own body, which it possesses only in part; and so
being delighted by corporeal forms and motions, because it has not the
things themselves within itself, and because it is wrapped up in their
images, which it has fixed in the memory, and is foully polluted by
fornication of the phantasy, while it refers all its functions to
those ends, for which it curiously seeks corporeal and temporal things
through the senses of the body, either it affects with swelling
arrogance to be more excellent than other souls that are given up to
the corporeal senses, or it is plunged into a foul whirlpool of carnal
pleasure.
Footnotes
[766] Ecclus. x. 15
[767] 1 Tim. vi. 10
Chapter 10.--The Lowest Degradation Reached by Degrees.
15. When the soul then consults either for itself or for others with a
good will towards perceiving the inner and higher things, such as are
possessed in a chaste embrace, without any narrowness or envy, not
individually, but in common by all who love such things; then even if
it be deceived in anything, through ignorance of things temporal (for
its action in this case is a temporal one), and if it does not hold
fast to that mode of acting which it ought, the temptation is but one
common to man. And it is a great thing so to pass through this life,
on which we travel, as it were, like a road on our return home, that
no temptation may take us, but what is common to man. [768] For this
is a sin, without the body, and must not be reckoned fornication, and
on that account is very easily pardoned. But when the soul does
anything in order to attain those things which are perceived through
the body, through lust of proving or of surpassing or of handling
them, in order that it may place in them its final good, then whatever
it does, it does wickedly, and commits fornication, sinning against
its own body: [769] and while snatching from within the deceitful
images of corporeal things, and combining them by vain thought, so
that nothing seems to it to be divine, unless it be of such a kind as
this; by selfish greediness it is made fruitful in errors, and by
selfish prodigality it is emptied of strength. Yet it would not leap
on at once from the commencement to such shameless and miserable
fornication, but, as it is written, "He that contemneth small things,
shall fall by little and little." [770]
Footnotes
[768] 1 Cor. x. 13
[769] 1 Cor. vi. 18
[770] Ecclus. xix. 1
Chapter 11.--The Image of the Beast in Man.
16. For as a snake does not creep on with open steps, but advances by
the very minutest efforts of its several scales; so the slippery
motion of falling away [from what is good] takes possession of the
negligent only gradually, and beginning from a perverse desire for the
likeness of God, arrives in the end at the likeness of beasts. Hence
it is that being naked of their first garment, they earned by
mortality coats of skins. [771] For the true honor of man is the image
and likeness of God, which is not preserved except it be in relation
to Him by whom it is impressed. The less therefore that one loves what
is one's own, the more one cleaves to God. But through the desire of
making trial of his own power, man by his own bidding falls down to
himself as to a sort of intermediate grade. And so, while he wishes to
be as God is, that is, under no one, he is thrust on, even from his
own middle grade, by way of punishment, to that which is lowest, that
is, to those things in which beasts delight: and thus, while his honor
is the likeness of God, but his dishonor is the likeness of the beast,
"Man being in honor abideth not: he is compared to the beasts that are
foolish, and is made like to them." [772] By what path, then, could he
pass so great a distance from the highest to the lowest, except
through his own intermediate grade? For when he neglects the love of
wisdom, which remains always after the same fashion, and lusts after
knowledge by experiment upon things temporal and mutable, that
knowledge puffeth up, it does not edify: [773] so the mind is
overweighed and thrust out, as it were, by its own weight from
blessedness; and learns by its own punishment, through that trial of
its own intermediateness, what the difference is between the good it
has abandoned and the bad to which it has committed itself; and having
thrown away and destroyed its strength, it cannot return, unless by
the grace of its Maker calling it to repentance, and forgiving its
sins. For who will deliver the unhappy soul from the body of this
death, unless the grace of God through Jesus Christ our Lord? [774] of
which grace we will discourse in its place, so far as He Himself
enables us.
Footnotes
[771] Gen. iii. 21
[772] Ps. xlix. 12
[773] 1 Cor. viii. 1
[774] Rom. vii. 24, 25
Chapter 12.--There is a Kind of Hidden Wedlock in the Inner Man.
Unlawful Pleasures of the Thoughts.
17. Let us now complete, so far as the Lord helps us, the discussion
which we have undertaken, respecting that part of reason to which
knowledge belongs, that is, the cognizance of things temporal and
changeable, which is necessary for managing the affairs of this life.
For as in the case of that visible wedlock of the two human beings who
were made first, the serpent did not eat of the forbidden tree, but
only persuaded them to eat of it; and the woman did not eat alone, but
gave to her husband, and they eat together; although she alone spoke
with the serpent, and she alone was led away by him: [775] so also in
the case of that hidden and secret kind of wedlock, which is
transacted and discerned in a single human being, the carnal, or as I
may say, since it is directed to the senses of the body, the sensuous
movement of the soul, which is common to us with beasts, is shut off
from the reason of wisdom. For certainly bodily things are perceived
by the sense of the body; but spiritual things, which are eternal and
unchangeable, are understood by the reason of wisdom. But the reason
of knowledge has appetite very near to it: seeing that what is called
the science or knowledge of actions reasons concerning the bodily
things which are perceived by the bodily sense; if well, in order that
it may refer that knowledge to the end of the chief good; but if ill,
in order that it may enjoy them as being such good things as those
wherein it reposes with a false blessedness. Whenever, then, that
carnal or animal sense introduces into this purpose of the mind which
is conversant about things temporal and corporeal, with a view to the
offices of a man's actions, by the living force of reason, some
inducement to enjoy itself, that is, to enjoy itself as if it were
some private good of its own, not as the public and common, which is
the unchangeable, good; then, as it were, the serpent discourses with
the woman. And to consent to this allurement, is to eat of the
forbidden tree. But if that consent is satisfied by the pleasure of
thought alone, but the members are so restrained by the authority of
higher counsel that they are not yielded as instruments of
unrighteousness unto sin; [776] this, I think, is to be considered as
if the woman alone should have eaten the forbidden food. But if, in
this consent to use wickedly the things which are perceived through
the senses of the body, any sin at all is so determined upon, that if
there is the power it is also fulfilled by the body; then that woman
must be understood to have given the unlawful food to her husband with
her, to be eaten together. For it is not possible for the mind to
determine that a sin is not only to be thought of with pleasure, but
also to be effectually committed, unless also that intention of the
mind yields, and serves the bad action, with which rests the chief
power of applying the members to an outward act, or of restraining
them from one.
18. And yet, certainly, when the mind is pleased in thought alone with
unlawful things, while not indeed determining that they are to be
done, but yet holding and pondering gladly things which ought to have
been rejected the very moment they touched the mind, it cannot be
denied to be a sin, but far less than if it were also determined to
accomplished it in outward act. And therefore pardon must be sought
for such thoughts too, and the breast must be smitten, and it must be
said, "Forgive us our debts;" and what follows must be done, and must
be joined in our prayer, "As we also forgive our debtors." [777] For
it is not as it was with those two first human beings, of which each
one bare his own person; and so, if the woman alone had eaten the
forbidden food, she certainly alone would have been smitten with the
punishment of death: it cannot, I say, be so said also in the case of
a single human being now, that if the thought, remaining alone, be
gladly fed with unlawful pleasures, from which it ought to turn away
directly, while yet there is no determination that the bad actions are
to be done, but only that they are retained with pleasure in
remembrance, the woman as it were can be condemned without the man.
Far be it from us to believe this. For here is one person, one human
being, and he as a whole will be condemned, unless those things which,
as lacking the will to do, and yet having the will to please the mind
with them, are perceived to be sins of thought alone, are pardoned
through the grace of the Mediator. [778]
19. This reasoning, then, whereby we have sought in the mind of each
several human being a certain rational wedlock of contemplation and
action, with functions distributed through each severally, yet with
the unity of the mind preserved in both; saving meanwhile the truth of
that history which divine testimony hands down respecting the first
two human beings, that is, the man and his wife, from whom the human
species is propagated; [779] --this reasoning, I say, must be listened
to only thus far, that the apostle may be understood to have intended
to signify something to be sought in one individual man, by assigning
the image of God to the man only, and not also to the woman, although
in the merely different sex of two human beings.
Footnotes
[775] Gen. iii. 1-6
[776] Rom. vi. 13
[777] Matt. vi. 12
[778] [Augustin here teaches that the inward lust is guilt as well as
the outward action prompted by it. This is in accordance with Matt. v.
28; Acts viii. 21-22; Rom. vii. 7; James i. 14.--W.G.T.S.]
[779] [Augustin means, that while he has given an allegorical and
mystical interpretation to the narrative of the fall, in Genesis, he
also holds to its historical sense.--W.G.T.S.]
Chapter 13.--The Opinion of Those Who Have Thought that the Mind Was
Signified by the Man, the Bodily Sense by the Woman.
20. Nor does it escape me, that some who before us were eminent
defenders of the Catholic faith and expounders of the word of God,
while they looked for these two things in one human being, whose
entire soul they perceived to be a sort of excellent paradise,
asserted that the man was the mind, but that the woman was the bodily
sense. And according to this distribution, by which the man is assumed
to be the mind, but the woman the bodily sense, all things seem aptly
to agree together if they are handled with due attention: unless that
it is written, that in all the beasts and flying things there was not
found for man an helpmate like to himself; and then the woman was made
out of his side. [780] And on this account I, for my part, have not
thought that the bodily sense should be taken for the woman, which we
see to be common to ourselves and to the beasts; but I have desired to
find something which the beasts had not; and I have rather thought the
bodily sense should be understood to be the serpent, whom we read to
have been more subtle than all beasts of the field. [781] For in those
natural good things which we see are common to ourselves and to the
irrational animals, the sense excels by a kind of living power; not
the sense of which it is written in the epistle addressed to the
Hebrews, where we read, that "strong meat belongeth to them that are
of full age, even those who by reason of use have their senses
exercised to discern both good and evil;" [782] for these "senses"
belong to the rational nature and pertain to the understanding; but
that sense which is divided into five parts in the body, through which
corporeal species and motion is perceived not only by ourselves, but
also by the beasts.
21. But whether that the apostle calls the man the image and glory of
God, but the woman the glory of the man, [783] is to be received in
this, or that, or in any other way; yet it is clear, that when we live
according to God, our mind which is intent on the invisible things of
Him ought to be fashioned with proficiency from His eternity, truth,
charity; but that something of our own rational purpose, that is, of
the same mind, must be directed to the using of changeable and
corporeal things, without which this life does not go on; not that we
may be conformed to this world, [784] by placing our end in such good
things, and by forcing the desire of blessedness towards them, but
that whatever we do rationally in the using of temporal things, we may
do it with the contemplation of attaining eternal things, passing
through the former, but cleaving to the latter.
Footnotes
[780] Gen. ii. 20-22
[781] Gen. iii. 1
[782] Heb. v. 14
[783] 1 Cor. xi. 7
[784] Rom. xii. 2
Chapter 14.--What is the Difference Between Wisdom and Knowledge. The
Worship of God is the Love of Him. How the Intellectual Cognizance of
Eternal Things Comes to Pass Through Wisdom.
For knowledge also has its own good measure, if that in it which puffs
up, or is wont to puff up, is conquered by love of eternal things,
which does not puff up, but, as we know, edifieth. [785] Certainly
without knowledge the virtues themselves, by which one lives rightly,
cannot be possessed, by which this miserable life may be so governed,
that we may attain to that eternal life which is truly blessed.
22. Yet action, by which we use temporal things well, differs from
contemplation of eternal things; and the latter is reckoned to wisdom,
the former to knowledge. For although that which is wisdom can also be
called knowledge, as the apostle too speaks, where he says, "Now I
know in part, but then shall I know even as also I am known;" [786]
when doubtless he meant his words to be understood of the knowledge of
the contemplation of God, which will be the highest reward of the
saints; yet where he says, "For to one is given by the Spirit the word
of wisdom, to another the word of knowledge by the same Spirit," [787]
certainly he distinguishes without doubt these two things, although he
does not there explain the difference, nor in what way one may be
discerned from the other. But having examined a great number of
passages from the Holy Scriptures, I find it written in the Book of
Job, that holy man being the speaker, "Behold, piety, that is wisdom;
but to depart from evil is knowledge." [788] In thus distinguishing,
it must be understood that wisdom belongs to contemplation, knowledge
to action. For in this place he meant by piety the worship of God,
which in Greek is called theosebeia. For the sentence in the Greek
mss. has that word. And what is there in eternal things more excellent
than God, of whom alone the nature is unchangeable? And what is the
worship of Him except the love of Him, by which we now desire to see
Him, and we believe and hope that we shall see Him; and in proportion
as we make progress, see now through a glass in an enigma, but then in
clearness? For this is what the Apostle Paul means by "face to face."
[789] This is also what John says, "Beloved, now we are the sons of
God, and it doth not yet appear what we shall be; but we know that,
when He shall appear, we shall be like Him; for we shall see Him as He
is." [790] Discourse about these and the like subjects seems to me to
be the discourse itself of wisdom. But to depart from evil, which Job
says is knowledge, is without doubt of temporal things. Since it is in
reference to time [and this world] that we are in evil, from which we
ought to abstain that we may come to those good eternal things. And
therefore, whatsoever we do prudently, boldly, temperately, and
justly, belongs to that knowledge or discipline wherewith our action
is conversant in avoiding evil and desiring good; and so also,
whatsoever we gather by the knowledge that comes from inquiry, in the
way of examples either to be guarded against or to be imitated, and in
the way of necessary proofs respecting any subject, accommodated to
our use.
23. When a discourse then relates to these things, I hold it to be a
discourse belonging to knowledge, and to be distinguished from a
discourse belonging to wisdom, to which those things belong, which
neither have been, nor shall be, but are; and on account of that
eternity in which they are, are said to have been, and to be, and to
be about to be, without any changeableness of times. For neither have
they been in such way as that they should cease to be, nor are they
about to be in such way as if they were not now; but they have always
had and always will have that very absolute being. And they abide, but
not as if fixed in some place as are bodies; but as intelligible
things in incorporeal nature, they are so at hand to the glance of the
mind, as things visible or tangible in place are to the sense of the
body. And not only in the case of sensible things posited in place,
there abide also intelligible and incorporeal reasons of them apart
from local space; but also of motions that pass by in successive
times, apart from any transit in time, there stand also like reasons,
themselves certainly intelligible, and not sensible. And to attain to
these with the eye of the mind is the lot of few; and when they are
attained as much as they can be, he himself who attains to them does
not abide in them, but is as it were repelled by the rebounding of the
eye itself of the mind, and so there comes to be a transitory thought
of a thing not transitory. And yet this transient thought is committed
to the memory through the instructions by which the mind is taught;
that the mind which is compelled to pass from thence, may be able to
return thither again; although, if the thought should not return to
the memory and find there what it had committed to it, it would be led
thereto like an uninstructed person, as it had been led before, and
would find it where it had first found it, that is to say, in that
incorporeal truth, whence yet once more it may be as it were written
down and fixed in the mind. For the thought of man, for example, does
not so abide in that incorporeal and unchangeable reason of a square
body, as that reason itself abides: if, to be sure, it could attain to
it at all without the phantasy of local space. Or if one were to
apprehend the rhythm of any artificial or musical sound, passing
through certain intervals of time, as it rested without time in some
secret and deep silence, it could at least be thought as long as that
song could be heard; yet what the glance of the mind, transient though
it was, caught from thence, and, absorbing as it were into a belly, so
laid up in the memory, over this it will be able to rumiuate in some
measure by recollection, and to transfer what it has thus learned into
systematic knowledge. But if this has been blotted out by absolute
forgetfulness, yet once again, under the guidance of teaching, one
will come to that which had altogether dropped away, and it will be
found such as it was.
Footnotes
[785] 1 Cor. viii. 1
[786] 1 Cor. xiii. 12
[787] 1 Cor. xii. 8
[788] Job xxviii. 8
[789] 1 Cor. xiii. 12
[790] 1 John iii. 2
Chapter 15.--In Opposition to the Reminiscence of Plato and
Pythagoras. Pythagoras the Samian. Of the Difference Between Wisdom
and Knowledge, and of Seeking the Trinity in the Knowledge of Temporal
Things.
24. And hence that noble philosopher Plato endeavored to persuade us
that the souls of men lived even before they bare these bodies; and
that hence those things which are learnt are rather remembered, as
having been known already, than taken into knowledge as things new.
For he has told us that a boy, when questioned I know not what
respecting geometry, replied as if he were perfectly skilled in that
branch of learning. For being questioned step by step and skillfully,
he saw what was to be seen, and said that which he saw. [791] But if
this had been a recollecting of things previously known, then
certainly every one, or almost every one, would not have been able so
to answer when questioned. For not every one was a geometrician in the
former life, since geometricians are so few among men that scarcely
one can be found anywhere. But we ought rather to believe, that the
intellectual mind is so formed in its nature as to see those things,
which by the disposition of the Creator are subjoined to things
intelligible in a natural order, by a sort of incorporeal light of an
unique kind; as the eye of the flesh sees things adjacent to itself in
this bodily light, of which light it is made to be receptive, and
adapted to it. For none the more does this fleshly eye, too,
distinguish black things from white without a teacher, because it had
already known them before it was created in this flesh. Why, lastly,
is it possible only in intelligible things that any one properly
questioned should answer according to any branch of learning, although
ignorant of it? Why can no one do this with things sensible, except
those which he has seen in this his present body, or has believed the
information of others who knew them, whether somebody's writings or
words? For we must not acquiesce in their story, who assert that the
Samian Pythagoras recollected some things of this kind, which he had
experienced when he was previously here in another body; and others
tell yet of others, that they experienced something of the same sort
in their minds: but it may be conjectured that these were untrue
recollections, such as we commonly experience in sleep, when we fancy
we remember, as though we had done or seen it, what we never did or
saw at all; and that the minds of these persons, even though awake,
were affected in this way at the suggestion of malignant and deceitful
spirits, whose care it is to confirm or to sow some false belief
concerning the changes of souls, in order to deceive men. This, I say,
may be conjectured from this, that if they really remembered those
things which they had seen here before, while occupying other bodies,
the same thing would happen to many, nay to almost all; since they
suppose that as the dead from the living, so, without cessation and
continually, the living are coming into existence from the dead; as
sleepers from those that are awake, and those that are awake from them
that sleep.
25. If therefore this is the right distinction between wisdom and
knowledge, that the intellectual cognizance of eternal things belongs
to wisdom, but the rational cognizance of temporal things to
knowledge, it is not difficult to judge which is to be preferred or
postponed to which. But if we must employ some other distinction by
which to know these two apart, which without doubt the apostle teaches
us are different, saying, "To one is given by the Spirit the word of
wisdom; to another the word of knowledge, by the same Spirit:" still
the difference between those two which we have laid down is a most
evident one, in that the intellectual cognizance of eternal things is
one thing, the rational cognizance of temporal things another; and no
one doubts but that the former is to be preferred to the latter. As
then we leave behind those things which belong to the outer man, and
desire to ascend within from those things which we have in common with
beasts, before we come to the cognizance of things intelligible and
supreme, which are eternal, the rational cognizance of temporal things
presents itself. Let us then find a trinity in this also, if we can,
as we found one in the senses of the body, and in those things which
through them entered in the way of images into our soul or spirit; so
that instead of corporeal things which we touch by corporeal sense,
placed as they are without us, we might have resemblances of bodies
impressed within on the memory from which thought might be formed,
while the will as a third united them; just as the sight of the eyes
was formed from without, which the will applied to the visible thing
in order to produce vision, and united both, while itself also added
itself thereto as a third. But this subject must not be compressed
into this book; so that in that which follows, if God help, it may be
suitably examined, and the conclusions to which we come may be
unfolded.
Footnotes
[791] [This fine specimen of the "obstetric method" of Socrates is
given in Plato's dialogue, Meno.--W.G.T.S.]
Also, see links to 600+ other Augustine Manuscripts:
/believe/txv/earlyche.htm
/believe/txv/earlychf.htm
/believe/txv/earlychg.htm
/believe/txv/earlychh.htm
/believe/txv/earlychi.htm
/believe/txv/earlychj.htm
/believe/txv/earlychk.htm
/believe/txv/earlychl.htm
/believe/txv/earlychm.htm
/believe/txv/earlychn.htm
E-mail to: BELIEVE
The main BELIEVE web-page (and the index to subjects) is at:
BELIEVE Religious Information Source - By Alphabet
http://mb-soft.com/believe/indexaz.html